Difference between revisions of "Vol-3197/short1"
Jump to navigation
Jump to search
(modified through wikirestore by wf) |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
=Paper= | =Paper= | ||
+ | |||
{{Paper | {{Paper | ||
|id=Vol-3197/short1 | |id=Vol-3197/short1 | ||
− | | | + | |wikidataid=Q117341496 |
|title=Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility | |title=Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility | ||
|pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short1.pdf | |pdfUrl=https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short1.pdf | ||
+ | |dblpUrl=https://dblp.org/rec/conf/nmr/BakerM22 | ||
|volume=Vol-3197 | |volume=Vol-3197 | ||
+ | |storemode=property | ||
|authors=Clayton K. Baker,Thomas Meyer | |authors=Clayton K. Baker,Thomas Meyer | ||
− | |||
}} | }} | ||
+ | =Freitext= | ||
==Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility== | ==Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility== | ||
<pdf width="1500px">https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short1.pdf</pdf> | <pdf width="1500px">https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short1.pdf</pdf> |
Revision as of 16:25, 30 March 2023
Paper
Paper | |
---|---|
edit | |
description | |
id | Vol-3197/short1 |
wikidataid | Q117341496→Q117341496 |
title | Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility |
pdfUrl | https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short1.pdf |
dblpUrl | https://dblp.org/rec/conf/nmr/BakerM22 |
volume | Vol-3197→Vol-3197 |
session | → |
Freitext
Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility
Asking Human Reasoners to Judge Postulates of Belief Change for Plausibility (Extended Abstract) Clayton K. Baker* , Thomas Meyer University of Cape Town and Centre for Artificial Intelligence (CAIR), Cape Town, South Africa Abstract Empirical methods have been used to test whether human reasoning conforms to models of reasoning in logic-based artificial intelligence. This work investigates through surveys whether postulates of belief revision and update are plausible with human reasoners. The results show that participants’ reasoning tend to be consistent with the postulates of belief revision and belief update when judging the premises and conclusion of the postulate separately. Keywords revision postulates, update postulates, human reasoning, survey 1. Introduction human reasoning is consistent with postulates, advanced by Alchourrón, Gärdenfors and Makinson (AGM) [8], for It has been shown that human reasoning displays non- belief revision. To enable comparison, we also hypothe- monotonicity, but the methodologies that test this rela- sise that human reasoning is consistent with postulates, tionship differ within the AI community. An example advanced by Katsuno and Mendelzon (KM) [9], for rea- [1] of one approach is through surveys in which English soning with belief update. We investigate the hypotheses translations of the postulates of defeasible reasoning were at the postulate level and at the system level. We use judged for plausibility by human reasoners. As another the language of propositional logic in the formulation example, a combined approach [2] was also used to inves- of our postulates to construct logically closed belief sets. tigate the link between formal theories of non-monotonic Additionally, we note that once our hypotheses are tested reasoning and the extent to which humans reason defea- using propositional logic as the underlying language, our sibly. The combined approach involved a theoretical and results can be lifted to other forms of logic. This work empirical analysis. In the theoretical analysis, the predic- extends previous work that investigated postulates of tions of each system was compared using the Suppression defeasible reasoning [10] and belief change [11] with Task [3], a logical experiment used in the psychology human reasoners via surveys. Furthermore, this work is community in which subjects appear to retract valid logi- an extended abstracted of a paper that is currently under cal inferences when subjects gain new information. In the review for a special issue of the Journal of Applied Logic. empirical analysis, three experiments were used to test the predictions of each system, as well as the inferences of human reasoners, with strict and defeasible knowl- 2. Background edge. While there are empirical studies that investigated the relationship between non-monotonic reasoning with 2.1. Belief Revision human reasoning, the relationship between belief change The first form of belief change we investigated was revi- and human reasoning has been primarily studied from a sion. It is an approach to reasoning with changing beliefs theoretical perspective, e.g. in classical logic [4], prob- under the assumption that the world did not undergo a ability and possibility theory [5], ontologies [6] and fundamental change. It is characterised by a belief set 𝒦, abstract argumentation [7]. Our first hypothesis is that a revision operation * and reasoning rules referred to as NMR’22: 20th International Workshop on Non-Monotonic Reasoning, postulates. A belief set is a set of propositional formulas August 07-09, 2022, Haifa, Israel closed under logical consequence. A revision operation * Corresponding author. allows a reasoner to add new information to his beliefs $ bkrcla003@myuct.ac.za (C. K. Baker); tmeyer@cs.uct.ac.za if the new information is consistent with his beliefs. A (T. Meyer) https://tinyurl.com/5n6vuyp7 (C. K. Baker); revision operation also allows a reasoner to add an ex- https://tinyurl.com/5ejbf2vr (T. Meyer) ception to his beliefs to account for the situation where � 0000-0002-3157-9989 (C. K. Baker); 0000-0003-2204-6969 this exception or new information is inconsistent with (T. Meyer) his beliefs. Moreover, the result of a revision operation © 2022 Copyright for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Commons License Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0). must always be that a reasoner’s beliefs do not contradict CEUR Workshop Proceedings http://ceur-ws.org ISSN 1613-0073 CEUR Workshop Proceedings (CEUR-WS.org) 139 �one another. There are eight postulates in the AGM [8] then it is a partial preorder. A preorder is total if 𝑎 ≤ 𝑏 belief revision framework. (R1)–(R6) correspond to the or 𝑏 ≤ 𝑎 for all 𝑎, 𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 . A revision operator satisfies core rationality postulates and the (R7)–(R8) correspond postulates (R1)–(R6) using the notion of a total preorder to supplementary postulates. on interpretations while an update operator satisfies pos- tulates (U1)–(U6) using the notion of a partial preorder (R1) 𝒦 * 𝜇 implies 𝜇 on interpretations. By replacing postulates (U6) and (U7) (R2) If 𝒦 ∧ 𝜇 is satisfiable, then 𝒦 * 𝜇 ≡ 𝒦 ∧ 𝜇 with a new postulate (U9), the class of update operators (R3) If 𝜇 is satisfiable, then 𝒦 * 𝜇 is also satisfiable can be designed using total preorders. The second and (R4) If 𝒦1 ≡ 𝒦2 and 𝜇1 ≡ 𝜇2 , then 𝒦1 *𝜇1 ≡ 𝒦2 *𝜇2 more important difference between revision and update (R5) (𝒦 * 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 implies 𝒦 * (𝜇 ∧ 𝜑) is that, in the case of update, a different ordering is in- (R6) If (𝒦 * 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 is satisfiable, then 𝒦 * (𝜇 ∧ 𝜑) duced by each model of 𝒦, while for revision, only one implies (𝒦 * 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 ordering is induced by the whole of 𝒦. (R7) If 𝒦 * 𝜇1 implies 𝜇2 and 𝒦 * 𝜇2 implies 𝜇1 , then 𝒦 * 𝜇1 is equivalent to 𝒦 * 𝜇2 (R8) (𝒦 * 𝜇1 ) ∧ (𝒦 * 𝜇2 ) implies 𝒦 * (𝜇1 ∨ 𝜇2 ) 3. Methodology Our empirical investigation took place through four ex- 2.2. Belief Update periments. In the first experiment, we prepared a survey of 30 general statements about the world for participants The next form of belief change we investigated was up- to evaluate for clarity and bias. 7 participants had to com- date. It is an approach to reasoning with changing beliefs plete a table in which they identified statements with am- after some fundamental shift in the world occurred. It biguous language and biased examples. In the second ex- is characterised by a belief set 𝒦, an update operation ◇ periment, we prepared a survey of 30 general statements and postulates for reasoning. As with revision, 𝒦 refers about the world taken from refining the material in the to a logically closed set of propositional formulas. When first experiment. 30 participants evaluated the degree to we update 𝒦 with new information 𝜇, we are saying that which they believed each of the statements in the survey we used to believe 𝒦, we know now that 𝜇 holds, and and explained their answers. In the third experiment, we we need to modify 𝒦 by adding 𝜇, acknowledging that prepared a survey of English statements corresponding we may have been wrong if 𝜇 contradicts 𝒦. There are to translations of the AGM postulates for belief revision. nine postulates in the KM [9] belief update framework. 35 participants on Mechanical Turk (MTurk) evaluated (U1) 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇 implies 𝜇 the degree to which they believed each statement in the (U2) If 𝒦 implies 𝜇 then 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇 is equivalent to 𝒦 survey. We tested our hypothesis statistically and deter- (U3) If both 𝒦 and 𝜇 are satisfiable then 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇 is also mined whether the association between the premises and satisfiable the conclusion for each postulate holds for the general (U4) If 𝒦1 ↔ 𝒦2 and 𝜇1 ↔ 𝜇2 then 𝒦1 ◇ 𝜇1 ↔ English-speaking reasoner. In the last experiment, we 𝒦2 ◇ 𝜇2 used the same material from the belief revision experi- ment to instantiate the KM belief update postulates. The (U5) (𝒦 ◇ 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 implies 𝒦 ◇ (𝜇 ∧ 𝜑) experimental setup followed a similar approach to the (U6) If 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇1 implies 𝜇2 and 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇2 implies 𝜇1 then belief revision experiment. We obtained ethical clearance 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇1 ↔ 𝒦 ◇ 𝜇2 from the Faculty of Science Ethics Research Committee (U7) If 𝒦 is complete then (𝒦 ◇ 𝜇1 ) ∧ (𝒦 ◇ 𝜇2 ) implies at the University of Cape Town. We include the consent 𝒦 ◇ (𝜇1 ∨ 𝜇2 ) forms and a link to our data management plan in our (U8) (𝒦1 ∨ 𝒦2 ) ◇ 𝜇 ↔ (𝒦1 ◇ 𝜇) ∨ (𝒦2 ◇ 𝜇) Github project repository, linked in Appendix A. For (U9) If 𝒦 is complete and (𝒦 ◇ 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 is satisfiable then the bulk of our reasoning experiments, we used Google 𝒦 ◇ (𝜇 ∧ 𝜑) implies (𝒦 ◇ 𝜇) ∧ 𝜑 Forms to design our surveys, and we used Mechanical Revision and update differ from non-monotonic logic Turk to crowdsource our data collection. using the concept of orders on interpretations. A ho- mogeneous relation ≤ on some given set 𝑃 , so that by 4. Results definition ≤ is some subset of 𝑃 × 𝑃 and the notation 𝑎 ≤ 𝑏 is used in place of (𝑎, 𝑏) ∈ 𝑃 , is called a preorder In this work, we investigated the endorsements of each if the relation is also transitive and reflexive. A reflexive component of the AGM postulates when formulated as relation has the property that 𝑎 ≤ 𝑎 for all 𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 . A material implication statements. We found evidence for transitive relation has the property that if 𝑎 ≤ 𝑏 and whether or not the participants found our concrete instan- 𝑏 ≤ 𝑐 then 𝑎 ≤ 𝑐 for all 𝑎, 𝑏, 𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 . If a preorder is also tiations of the AGM postulates plausible. We determined anti-symmetric, that is, 𝑎 ≤ 𝑏 and 𝑏 ≤ 𝑎 implies 𝑎 = 𝑏, whether the postulates hold in general. The results show 140 �that the participants’ reasoning tends to be consistent tionships. The empirical part will focus on identifying with the 9 AGM postulates, with the significance of the as- representations of the postulates that support both the sociation between the endorsement of the premises and theory and the beliefs of human reasoners. It will in- the endorsement of the conclusion ranging from non- volve the development of an online reasoning tool that significant to highly significant. The number of logical automates the production and presentation of structured violations per postulate is generally low with a range of reasoning examples in a survey setting. The structured 0 to 4 violations (< 12% of participants). The exception reasoning examples will depict the static and dynamic is postulate (R5) with 54,29% (19 participants) endorsing nature of changing beliefs in terms of a revision and an the premises, but not the conclusion. update, respectively. In turn, the tailored surveys created We also investigated the endorsements of each compo- using the reasoning tool can be used to elicit responses nent of the KM postulates when formulated as material from human reasoners, the design of which improves implication statements. We found evidence for whether upon the limitations of question types from conventional or not the participants found our concrete instantiations survey platforms like Google Forms and Microsoft Forms. of the KM postulates plausible. We determined whether Furthermore, non-parameterised statistical methods, that the postulates hold in general. The results show that the is, methods that do not assume how the sample data is participants’ reasoning tends to be consistent with the 9 distributed, e.g. the Wilcoxon signed-rank test [12, 13], postulates of KM belief update, with the significance of will be used to interpret the significance of the postulates the association between the endorsement of the premises of belief change, as found by human reasoners. and the endorsement of the conclusion ranging from non- significant to highly significant. The number of logical violations per postulate is generally low as well with a Acknowledgments range of 0 to 8 violations (< 23% of participants). The We wish to express our sincere gratitude and appreciation exception is postulate (U8) with 48,57% (17 participants) to the DSI – CSIR Interbursary Support (IBS) Programme endorsing the premises, but not the conclusion. and the Centre for Artificial Intelligence Research (CAIR) for financial support. 5. Conclusions and Future Work Our work builds on previous empirical studies involv- References ing human subjects who are tasked with reasoning non- [1] R. Neves, J. Bonnefon, E. Raufaste, An empirical test monotonically. We created a reproducible approach for of patterns for nonmonotonic inference, Annals empirically investigating the plausibility of postulates of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence 34 (2002) of belief change. This approach accounts for the effect 107–130. of the premises and conclusion of each postulate and [2] M. Ragni, C. Eichhorn, T. Bock, G. Kern-Isberner, determines whether the overall postulate is found plau- A. Tse, Formal nonmonotonic theories and prop- sible with statistically significant evidence. We applied erties of human defeasible reasoning, Minds this approach to the formal theory of belief revision and and Machines 27 (2017) 79–117. doi:10.1007/ update. We hypothesised that human belief change is s11023-016-9414-1. consistent with the AGM postulates of belief revision [3] R. M. Byrne, Suppressing valid inferences with and the KM postulates of belief update. The results show conditionals, Cognition 31 (1989) 61–83. that the participants’ reasoning tends to be consistent [4] F. Lévy, A survey of belief revision and updating in with the 8 AGM postulates, (R1)–(R8), with the signifi- classical logic, International Journal of Intelligent cance of the association between the endorsement of the Systems 9 (1994) 29–59. premises and the endorsement of the conclusion ranging [5] D. Dubois, H. Prade, A survey of belief revision from non-significant to highly significant. The results and updating rules in various uncertainty models, also show that the participants’ reasoning tends to be International Journal of Intelligent Systems 9 (1994) consistent with the 9 KM postulates, (U1)–(U9), with the 61–100. significance of the association between the endorsement [6] C. Boutilier, N. Friedman, J. Y. Halpern, Belief revi- of the premises and the endorsement of the conclusion sion with unreliable observations, in: AAAI/IAAI, ranging from non-significant to highly significant. 1998, pp. 127–134. In future work, we will refine our approach in the [7] S. Doutre, J.-G. Mailly, Constraints and changes: A following way. We will conduct a theoretical and em- survey of abstract argumentation dynamics, Argu- pirical investigation of the postulates of belief revision ment & Computation 9 (2018) 223–248. and update. The theoretical part will build on this work [8] C. E. Alchourrón, P. Gärdenfors, D. Makinson, On by exploring inter-postulate and inter-framework rela- the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction 141 � and revision functions, Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1985) 510–530. doi:10.2307/2274239. [9] H. Katsuno, A. O. Mendelzon, On the difference between updating a knowledge base and revising it, Belief revision (1991) 183. [10] C. Baker, C. Denny, P. Freund, T. Meyer, Cognitive defeasible reasoning: the extent to which forms of defeasible reasoning correspond with human reasoning, in: Proceedings of the First Southern African Conference for Artificial Intelligence Re- search (SACAIR 2020), CCIS, Springer, 2020, pp. 119–219. [11] C. Baker, T. Meyer, Belief change in human rea- soning: An empirical investigation on mturk, in: Proceedings of the Second Southern African Con- ference for Artificial Intelligence Research (SACAIR 2021), 2021, pp. 520–536. [12] X. Li, Y. Wu, M. Wei, Y. Guo, Z. Yu, H. Wang, Z. Li, H. Fan, A novel index of functional connectivity: phase lag based on wilcoxon signed rank test, Cog- nitive Neurodynamics 15 (2021) 621–636. [13] L. Zhou, Performance of corporate bankruptcy prediction models on imbalanced dataset: The effect of sampling methods, Knowledge-Based Systems 41 (2013) 16–25. A. Additional resources The Github repository for this work, containing supple- mentary material and code scripts, can be accessed via this URL, https://tinyurl.com/2p98m76n. 142 �