Vol-3197/paper9

From BITPlan ceur-ws Wiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Paper

Paper
edit
description  scientific paper published in CEUR-WS Volume 3197
id  Vol-3197/paper9
wikidataid  Q117341796β†’Q117341796
title  Argumentation Frameworks Induced by Assumption-Based Argumentation: Relating Size and Complexity
pdfUrl  https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/paper9.pdf
dblpUrl  https://dblp.org/rec/conf/nmr/Rapberger0W22
volume  Vol-3197β†’Vol-3197
session  β†’

Argumentation Frameworks Induced by Assumption-Based Argumentation: Relating Size and Complexity

load PDF

Argumentation Frameworks Induced by
Assumption-Based Argumentation: Relating Size and
Complexity
Anna Rapberger1 , Markus Ulbricht2 and Johannes P. Wallner3
1
  TU Wien, Institute of Logic and Computation
2
  Leipzig University, Department of Computer Science
3
  Graz University of Technology, Institute of Software Technology


                                             Abstract
                                             A key ingredient of computational argumentation in AI is the generation of arguments in favor or against claims under scrutiny.
                                             In this paper we look at the complexity of the argument generation procedure in the prominent structured formalism of
                                             assumption-based argumentation (ABA). We show several results connecting expressivity of ABA fragments and number
                                             of constructed arguments. First, for several NP-hard fragments of ABA, the number of generated arguments is not bounded
                                             polynomially. Even under equivalent rewritings of the given ABA framework there are situations where one cannot avoid an
                                             exponential blow-up. We establish a weaker notion of equivalence under which this blow-up can be avoided. As a general tool
                                             for analyzing ABA frameworks and resulting arguments and their conflicts, we extend results regarding dependency graphs of
                                             ABA frameworks, from which one can infer structural properties on the induced attacks among arguments.


1. Introduction                                                                                                                       assess the instantiated AF. Thus, many typical research
                                                                                                                                      questions can be answered out of the box after converting
Computational models of argumentation are a central ap-                                                                               the knowledge base. Moreover, since AFs are directed
proach within non-monotonic reasoning [1] with a variety                                                                              graphs, they are accessible and user-friendly; much infor-
of applications [2] in, e.g., legal or medical reasoning.                                                                             mation encoded in the knowledge base is made explicit
Key to many approaches to computational argumentation                                                                                 and clear within the graphical framework.
are formalisms in what is called structured argumenta-                                                                                   Let us consider the following situation. Suppose we
tion which specify formal argumentative workflows, with                                                                               plan to model the behavior of the propositional CNF-
assumption-based argumentation (ABA) [3], ASPIC+ [4],                                                                                 formula πœ‘ = (π‘₯1 ∨ Β¬π‘₯2 ) ∧ (Β¬π‘₯1 ∨ π‘₯2 ) via an ABA
defeasible logic programming (DeLP) [5], and deduc-                                                                                   knowledge base (see Section 2 for a formal introduction
tive argumentation [6] among the prominent approaches                                                                                 to ABA). For this, we identify πœ‘ with the set {𝐢1 , 𝐢2 }
in the field. Reasoning within these formalisms is of-                                                                                of clauses 𝐢1 = {π‘₯1 , Β¬π‘₯2 } and 𝐢2 = {Β¬π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 }. A
tentimes carried out by instantiating argument structures                                                                             natural representation would make use of assumptions
and conflicts among these arguments from (rule-based)                                                                                 corresponding to the four occurring literals, i.e. π’œ =
knowledge bases in a principled manner. The resulting                                                                                 {π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 , π‘₯β€²1 , π‘₯β€²2 }. Then, rules model satisfaction of the
arguments and (directed) conflicts are referred to as ar-                                                                             given clauses; we construct
gumentation frameworks (AFs) [7]. Argumentation se-
                                                                                                                                              π‘Ÿ 1 = 𝐢 1 ← π‘₯1 .          π‘Ÿ3 = 𝐢2 ← π‘₯β€²1 .
mantics define argumentative acceptability on an AF s.t.
conclusions can be drawn for the original knowledge base.                                                                                     π‘Ÿ2 = 𝐢1 ← π‘₯β€²2 .           π‘Ÿ4 = 𝐢2 ← π‘₯2 .
   In the present paper, we will focus on ABA [8] which                                                                               with the intuitive meaning that e.g. 𝐢1 can be derived if π‘Ÿ1
is well studied and has applications in, e.g., decision mak-                                                                          or π‘Ÿ2 is applicable which in turn is the case if the assump-
ing [9, 10, 11]. Argumentative reasoning can be carried                                                                               tion π‘₯1 or the assumption Β¬π‘₯2 is set to true, respectively.
out by instantiating arguments as derivations in the given                                                                            Lastly, the rule β€œπ‘Ÿ5 = πœ‘ ← 𝐢1 , 𝐢2 .” models that πœ‘ can
rule base and attacks between arguments based on con-                                                                                 be derived if both 𝐢1 and 𝐢2 can. When constructing
traries among the derivations.                                                                                                        the argumentation framework corresponding to this ABA
   Constructing an AF corresponding to a given knowl-                                                                                 knowledge base, we would make the conditions under
edge base has several advantages. From a technical point                                                                              which πœ‘ can be derived (i.e. what satisfying assignments
of view, there is an abundance of research concerned with                                                                             to the formula exist) visible; indeed, among others, the
AFs (see [1] for an overview) which can be applied to                                                                                 following arguments would be obtained:
                                                                                                                                                  πœ‘              πœ‘           πœ‘            πœ‘
NMR 2022: 20th InternationalWorkshop on Non-Monotonic Reason-
ing, August 07–09, 2022, Haifa, Israel                                                                                                   𝐴1 : 𝑐1 𝑐2 𝐴3 : 𝑐1 𝑐2 𝐴2 : 𝑐1 𝑐2 𝐴4 : 𝑐1 𝑐2
                                       Β© 2022 Copyright for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Commons License
    CEUR
    Workshop
    Proceedings
                  http://ceur-ws.org
                  ISSN 1613-0073
                                       Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0).
                                       CEUR Workshop Proceedings (CEUR-WS.org)                                                                 π‘₯1 π‘₯β€²1         π‘₯β€²2 π‘₯β€²1      π‘₯1 π‘₯2        π‘₯β€²2 π‘₯2




                                                                                                                                 92
οΏ½We can now directly read off that e.g. {π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 } (see 𝐴3 )     on ABA via using AFs, both the size of the resulting
constitutes a satisfying assignment to πœ‘ since both 𝐢1 and      AF and complexity of the resulting AF can pose barri-
𝐢2 (and thus πœ‘) can be derived. We can also see that            ers to (automated) argumentative reasoning. On the one
{π‘₯1 , π‘₯β€²1 } would in principle infer πœ‘ as well, but this set    hand size and complexity of AFs are direct challenges
of literals does not correspond to a well-defined (partial)     for solvers [15, 16]. On the other hand, a large number
assignment; we can not set π‘₯1 to true and false simultane-      of arguments in an AF can be a barrier to methods sup-
ously. We thus see that constructing the arguments helps        porting argumentative explanations on the AF, due to the
visualizing the information encoded in the knowledge            sheer number of arguments. Therefore, investigating for-
base and makes certain relations explicit. Indeed, sim-         mal foundations which provide guidance how to encode
ply inspecting all arguments deriving πœ‘ suffices to decide      information, depending on the intended behavior of the
whether there is a satisfying assignment to our formula.        induced AF, is a worthwhile endeavor.
   However, since checking satisfiability of a given CNF-          The main contributions of the paper can be summarized
formula is the prototypical NP-complete problem, we             as follows.
expect that this procedure must come with computational
cost elsewhere. Indeed, many structured argumentation                β€’ We first deal with the case of infinite instantiated
formalisms (including ABA) suffer from the drawback                    AFs and show that one can restrict attention to
that the knowledge base gives rise to exponentially many               finite cores.
(or even an infinite amount of) arguments [12, 13, 14]. So,          β€’ We relate bounds on the given ABA instance to (i)
in a nutshell, the instantiated AF makes information within            size bounds and computability of the constructed
the knowledge base explicit, but requires many arguments               AF and (ii) complexity of reasoning.
to do so. This gives rise to the following question:                 β€’ We show that each ABA framework can be rewrit-
                                                                       ten in a way that reasoning in the induced AF is
        Is the argumentation framework induced                         tractable, while credulous acceptance of a target
        by an ABA knowledge base large in size,                        conclusion is preserved.
        but reasoning is easy?
                                                                     β€’ We present, for a fairly large class of ABA frame-
Although this idea is appealing in principle, the answer               works, a general transformation procedure to ob-
turns out to be negative in general: Even if we reduce our             tain a translated ABA framework which is equiva-
attention to the class of AFs induced by ABA knowledge                 lent under projection and has a polynomial-sized
bases, reasoning is still intractable in general. Nonethe-             AF. We present an impossibility result suggesting
less, we expect an underlying trade-off between size and               that the notion of equivalence cannot be strength-
complexity which is worth to be investigated. As a high                ened to full equivalence.
level observation we expect an ideal ABA knowledge base              β€’ We extend the notion of dependency graphs on
to                                                                     ABA frameworks (see, e.g., Craven and Toni,
                                                                       2016) to a general tool for investigating ABA
     β€’ induce a large AF, but with reasoning being simple,             frameworks able to check structural properties
       or                                                              inducing milder complexity, such as acyclic or
     β€’ a concise AF, in which reasoning is potentially                 odd-cycle free AFs.
       hard.

If the former is the case, then the instantiation proce-        2. Assumption-based
dure can help displaying relationships encoded within the
knowledge base, as it was the case for our CNF formula             Argumentation
πœ‘ from above. If on the other hand the latter case occurs,
                                                               We recall preliminaries for assumption-based argumen-
then the constructed AF is efficient and easy to capture
                                                               tation (ABA) [8, 3] and argumentation frameworks
visibly. In this paper, we will investigate this trade-off
                                                               (AFs) [7].
and examine the relationship between size and complexity
                                                                  The first ingredient of ABA is that of a deductive system
of the induced AF. Most notably, we will show that each
                                                               (β„’, β„›), with β„’ a formal language and β„› a set of inference
ABA framework can be transferred in a way that either
                                                               rules over β„’. In this work we assume that β„’ is a set of
reasoning becomes easy (Theorem 32) or the AF is of
                                                               atoms. A rule π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› is of the form 𝑠 ← π‘Ž1 , . . . , π‘Žπ‘›
polynomial size (Proposition 28), but reaching both goals
                                                               with π‘Žπ‘– ∈ β„’. A shorthand for the head of a rule π‘Ÿ is
simultaneously is not possible in general (Theorem 32).
                                                               defined by β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) = {𝑠}, and for the (possibly empty)
   In doing so, our goal is also contributing to a general
                                                               body via π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) = {π‘Ž1 , . . . , π‘Žπ‘› }. An ABA framework
formal understanding under which conditions a knowl-
                                                               contains a deductive system and specifies which atoms
edge base induces large AFs and which techniques might
                                                               are assumptions and what are contraries of assumptions.
help avoiding this blow-up. For carrying out reasoning




                                                           93
�Definition 1. An ABA framework is a tuple 𝐷 = 𝐴 does not attack itself. Set 𝐴 defends assumption set
(β„’, β„›, π’œ, ), where (β„’, β„›) is a deductive system, π’œ βŠ† β„’ 𝐡 βŠ† π’œ in 𝐷 iff for all 𝐢 βŠ† π’œ that attack 𝐡 it holds that
a non-empty set of assumptions, and a function map- 𝐴 attacks 𝐢.
ping assumptions π‘Ž ∈ π’œ to atoms 𝑠 ∈ β„’ (the contrary
function).                                                       In this paper, we focus on the central semantical con-
                                                              cept of admissibility.
    In this work, we focus on ABA frameworks which are
                                                          / π’œ Definition 4. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
(i) flat, i.e., for each rule π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› it holds that β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) ∈
(no assumptions can be derived), (ii) β„’, β„›, and π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) work. A set of assumptions 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ is admissible iff 𝐴 is
for each π‘Ÿ ∈ 𝑅 is finite, and (iii) each rule in β„› is stated conflict-free and 𝐴 defends itself.
explicitly (given as input).                                     We move on to tree-based arguments.
    Semantics of ABA frameworks can be defined on sub-
sets of the assumptions or via translation to arguments Definition 5. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
and attacks. Below, we recall both notions.                   work, and (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) and (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑) two tree-based argu-
    Arguments in an ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) ments based on 𝐷. Tree-based argument (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) attacks
are based on proof trees (derivations). Due to our focus on (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑) if there is an assumption 𝑏 ∈ 𝐡 s.t. 𝑏 = 𝑠.
computational aspects, we will in later sections consider
a different representation of arguments, hence we refer          Collecting all tree-based arguments and attacks based
to arguments based directly on proof trees as β€œtree-based     on  an ABA results in an argumentation framework corre-
arguments”. Formally, a tree-based argument, denoted by sponding to the given ABA.
𝐴 βŠ’β„› 𝑠, with 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ and 𝑠 ∈ β„’ based on 𝐷 is defined                 Definition 6. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
as a finite labeled rooted tree s.t. the root is labeled with      work. The pair (A, R) is called the argumentation frame-
𝑠, each leaf is labeled by an assumption π‘Ž ∈ π’œ or a                work (AF) corresponding to 𝐷 if A is the set of all tree-
dedicated symbol ⊀ ∈   / β„’ s.t. the set of all labels of leaves    based arguments based on 𝐷, and R is the set of all
is 𝐴, and each internal node is labeled with β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) of a          attacks based on 𝐷.
rule π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› s.t. the set of labels of children of this node
is equal to π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) or ⊀ if the body is empty. Moreover,              Below we recall the analogous notions of conflict-
if π‘Ž ∈ π’œ, then {π‘Ž} βŠ’β„› π‘Ž is also a tree-based argument              freeness, defense and admissibility in AFs.
(special case without using any derivation rules). In brief,
a tree-based argument represents a derivation using rules         Definition 7. Let 𝐷 be an ABA framework, 𝐹 = (A, R)
in β„› to derive 𝑠 starting from assumptions in π’œ. We say           the corresponding AF, and 𝐻 βŠ† A a set of tree-based
that 𝑠 is the claim of the tree-based argument. We remark         arguments of 𝐹 . The set 𝐻 is conflict-free (in 𝐹 ) if there
that there can be multiple tree-based arguments with the          are no arguments (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠), (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑) ∈ 𝐻 s.t. (𝐴 ⊒
same set of assumptions and claim.                                𝑠) attacks (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑). A conflict-free set 𝐻 defends an
   Given an ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ), deriv-                 argument (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) (in 𝐹 ) if for each argument (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑) ∈
ability for a set of assumptions 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ is defined via             A that attacks (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) it holds that there is an argument
Th 𝐷 (𝐴) = {𝑠 | there is a tree-based argument 𝐴′ βŠ’β„›              (𝐢 ⊒ 𝑒) ∈ 𝐻 s.t. (𝐢 ⊒ 𝑒) attacks (𝐡 ⊒ 𝑑). Moreover, 𝐻
𝑠, 𝐴′ βŠ† 𝐴}. That is, Th 𝐷 (𝐴) contains all atoms that             is admissible (in 𝐹 ) if it is conflict-free and defends itself.
can be derived (via tree-based arguments) using assump-       Claims of tree-based arguments are collected via
tions in 𝐴. We omit subscripts 𝐷 and β„› if clear from the  cl (𝐻) = {𝑠 | (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) ∈ 𝐻} for a set of tree-
context.                                                  based   arguments 𝐻, and assumptions via asms(𝐻) =
   We now recall conflicts, admissible sets, and subse-   ⋃︀
                                                             (π΄βŠ’π‘ )∈𝐻 𝐴.
quently the corresponding definitions on tree-based argu-     To clearly distinguish semantics, we say that 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ
ments.                                                    is an admissible assumption set (or an adm-assumption
Definition 2. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame- set) and that a set of tree-based arguments 𝐸 is an admis-
work, and 𝐴, 𝐡 βŠ† π’œ be two sets of assumptions. Assump- sible extension (or adm-extension for short). We refer
tion set 𝐴 attacks assumption set 𝐡 in 𝐷 if 𝑏 ∈ Th(𝐴) to all adm-assumption sets of 𝐷 via adm(𝐷), and to
for some 𝑏 ∈ 𝐡.                                           all adm-extensions of an AF 𝐹 by adm(𝐹 ). There is a
                                                          direct correspondence between semantics via assumption
   In words, an assumption set 𝐴 attacks assumption set sets and sets of tree-based arguments (see, e.g., Čyras
𝐡 if it is possible to derive from 𝐴 the contrary of some et al., 2018).
assumption in 𝐡.
                                                          Proposition 8. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
Definition 3. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame- work and 𝐹 = (A, R) the corresponding AF.
work. An assumption set 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ is conflict-free in 𝐷 iff




                                                              94
οΏ½     β€’ If 𝐸 ∈ adm(𝐷) then {(𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) | 𝐴 βŠ†                           and 𝑏 = π‘₯. There are infinitely (countably) many tree-
       𝐸, (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) is a tree-based argument in 𝐷} ∈                 based arguments based on 𝐷 (via chaining rules arbitrary
       adm(𝐹 ), and                                                many times), and argument {π‘Ž} ⊒ π‘Ž is attacked by all
     β€’ if 𝐻 ∈ adm(𝐹 ) then asms(𝐻) ∈ adm(𝐷).                       tree-based arguments concluding 𝑦 (of which there are
                                                                   infinitely many).
   An important reasoning task on ABA and AFs is cred-
ulous reasoning under admissibility. An atom 𝑠 is cred-               This leads to the simple observation stated next. That
ulously accepted under admissibility in an ABA 𝐷 iff               there are countably many tree-based arguments can be
there is an adm-assumption-set 𝐸 s.t. 𝑠 ∈ Th(𝐸). For a             seen since one can write (for a given ABA) each argument
given AF (A, R) and 𝛼 ∈ A, it holds that 𝛼 is credulously          as a string over a restricted alphabet.
accepted under admissibility in 𝐹 iff there is an adm-             Observation 11. Given an ABA framework, the corre-
extension 𝐻 containing 𝛼. We remark that credulous                 sponding AF can be (countably) infinite and non-finitary.
acceptance of tree-based arguments in a given AF can be
directly generalized to ask for acceptance of claims 𝑠 of             Nevertheless, as one can see intuitively in the example,
tree-based arguments, i.e., asking whether there is some           AFs corresponding to an ABA framework can be β€œcut
adm-extension containing some tree-based argument 𝛼                down” to a finite core by removing β€œduplicates” of ar-
with claim 𝑠.                                                      guments. This observation is sometimes assumed to be
   Complexity results for reasoning in ABA and AFs were            folklore in the research community and stated for other
established (see, e.g., DvoΕ™Γ‘k and Dunne, 2018, for an            forms of structured argumentation [12].
overview) when the corresponding structure is given (in               Let us formalize how to obtain such a duplicate-free
particular for AFs the full AF is given as input). For both        core. Tree-based arguments in an ABA framework are
assumption sets and extensions, credulous acceptance un-           defined as proof trees, with each argument (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) based
der admissibility is NP -complete.                                 on a set of assumptions and a claim. While rules are driv-
                                                                   ing derivability, they are not important when evaluating
Example 9. We formalize the introductory example. The              arguments: conflicts between arguments are solely spec-
ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) is given by                          ified via assumptions 𝐴 and claim 𝑠. A natural way to
                                                                   represent arguments is thus by using only 𝐴 and 𝑠. From
      β„’ = {𝑐1 , 𝑐2 , πœ‘} βˆͺ π’œ,
                                                                   now on, we mean by arguments pairs (𝐴, 𝑠) but insist that
      π’œ = {π‘₯1 , π‘₯β€²1 , π‘₯2 , π‘₯β€²2 } with π‘₯𝑖 = π‘₯′𝑖 , π‘₯′𝑖 = π‘₯𝑖 ,        there is a corresponding proof tree (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) in the given
                                                                   ABA framework. We call the resulting set of arguments
moreover, the rules β„› of the given ABA are                         the core of an ABA.
             𝑐 1 ← π‘₯1 ;     𝑐1 ← π‘₯β€²2 ;    𝑐2 ← π‘₯β€²1 ;          Definition 12. Let 𝐷            =   (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be
               𝑐2 ← π‘₯2 ; πœ‘ ← 𝑐1 , 𝑐2 .                        an  ABA      framework.     Let  A  = {(𝐴, 𝑠) |
                                                              there is a tree-based argument (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) in 𝐷}. An
It holds that each 𝐴 βŠ† π’œ is admissible whenever argument (𝐴, 𝑠) attacks an argument (𝐡, 𝑑) (in 𝐷) if
{π‘₯𝑖 , π‘₯′𝑖 } ΜΈβŠ† 𝐴 for 𝑖 ∈ {1, 2} (no β€œcomplementary lit- βˆƒπ‘ ∈ 𝐡 s.t. 𝑏 = 𝑠, with R being the set of all such attacks.
erals”). Moreover, the literal πœ‘ is credulously accepted The AF 𝐹 = (A, R) is called the core of 𝐷.
under admissibility, since, e.g. {π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 } is admissible and   Claims and assumptions of a set of arguments 𝐻 βŠ†
πœ‘ ∈ Th({π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 }).                                           A are defined similarly as for tree-based arguments:
                                                                   ⋃︀(𝐻) = {𝑠 | (𝐴, 𝑠) ∈ 𝐻} and asms(𝐻) =
                                                                   cl
3. Infinite AFs, Cores, and                                           (𝐴,𝑠)∈𝐻 𝐴. Given an ABA 𝐷 its corresponding AF 𝐹
                                                                   and core 𝐹 β€² , in addition to the core being finite it follows
   Representation                                                  directly that
In general it can be the case that an AF 𝐹 corresponding                β€’ for each tree-based argument (𝐴 ⊒ 𝑠) there is an
to a given ABA 𝐷 is not finite. We first recall some basic                argument (𝐴, 𝑠) and vice versa, and thus
properties of such (possibly) infinite corresponding AFs.               β€’ 𝐹 has an admissible set of tree-based arguments
   We say that an AF 𝐹 = (A, R) is infinite if A is infinite.             𝐻 with cl (𝐻) = 𝑆 and asms(𝐻) = 𝐴 iff 𝐹 β€² has
An AF 𝐹 is finitary [7] if it holds that each argument                    an admissible set of arguments 𝐻 β€² , cl (𝐻 β€² ) = 𝑆
𝛼 ∈ A is attacked by a finite number of arguments (but                    and asms(𝐻 β€² ) = 𝐴.
the overall number of arguments may still be infinite).
                                                  If one is not interested in the actual derivation of a claim,
Example 10. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame- representing an argument as a pair (𝐴, 𝑠) narrows down
work with π’œ = {π‘Ž, 𝑏}, β„’ = {π‘₯, 𝑦} βˆͺ π’œ, four rules the argument to the information required in order to con-
(π‘₯ ← π‘Ž), (π‘₯ ← π‘₯), (𝑦 ← 𝑦), and (𝑦 ← 𝑏), and π‘Ž = 𝑦 struct the corresponding AF (the core) and perform the




                                                              95
οΏ½standard reasoning tasks. To some extent surprising per-            4.1. Bounds and Complexity of
haps, we can find a complexity-theoretic result supporting               Reasoning
the intuition that the core is a more efficient representa-
tion: while deciding whether a proof tree constitutes a        First, we consider bounds on (i) the depth of chaining
tree-based argument for a given ABA is immediate, it is        rules and (ii) the size of bodies of rules. We show that
NP -hard to decide whether a pair (𝐴, 𝑠) occurs in the         restricting derivation-depth or rule-size does not yield
core.                                                          milder complexity regarding credulous reasoning under
                                                               admissibility.
Proposition 13. It is NP-hard to decide whether there is          Formally, an ABA 𝐷 is bounded by π‘˜-derivation-depth
a proof tree from a given set of assumptions to a given if each proof tree of 𝐷 has height at most π‘˜ (i.e., the
claim.                                                         longest path from assumptions to claim is at most π‘˜). A
                                                               rule of the form 𝑠 ← 𝑏1 , . . . , 𝑏𝑛 is bounded by π‘˜ if 𝑛 ≀ π‘˜;
Proof. Let πœ‘ = 𝑐1 ∧· Β· Β·βˆ§π‘π‘š be a Boolean formula in con-
                                                               an ABA 𝐷 is rule-size bounded by π‘˜ if each rule in 𝐷 is
junctive normal form over vocabulary 𝑋 = {π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 }
                                                               bounded by π‘˜.
with 𝐢 = {𝑐1 , . . . , π‘π‘š } the set of clauses. We construct
                                                                  In order to show that bounding derivation-depth is in-
an ABA framework 𝐷 with π’œ = 𝐢, atoms 𝐢 together
                                                               tractable, we reduce the Boolean Satisfiability Problem
with literals over 𝑋 and {𝑑π‘₯1 , . . . , 𝑑π‘₯𝑛 }, and the follow-
                                                               via the following reduction:
ing rules (note that β€œΒ¬π‘₯” is a symbol in ABA and has no
meaning attached to the negation sign):                        Reduction 14. Let πœ‘ = 𝑐1 ∧ Β· Β· Β· ∧ π‘π‘š be a Boolean for-
                                                               mula in conjunctive normal form (CNF) over clauses 𝐢 =
           π‘₯ ← {𝑐 ∈ 𝐢|π‘₯ ∈ 𝑐}, and
                                                               {𝑐1 , . . . , π‘π‘š } and Boolean variables 𝑋 = {π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 }.
         Β¬π‘₯ ← {𝑐 ∈ 𝐢|Β¬π‘₯ ∈ 𝑐} for each π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋                    Define 𝑋 β€² = {π‘₯β€² | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋}. Construct 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, )
          𝑑π‘₯ ← π‘₯ and 𝑑π‘₯ ← Β¬π‘₯ for each π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋                    by
          𝑓 ← 𝑑 π‘₯1 , . . . , 𝑑 π‘₯𝑛                                        β€’ β„’ = 𝑋 βˆͺ 𝑋 β€² βˆͺ 𝐢 βˆͺ {πœ‘},
Contraries are assigned to literals not appearing in any                 β€’ π’œ = 𝑋 βˆͺ 𝑋 β€²,
rules (for the task of argument construction, contraries are             β€’ π‘₯ = π‘₯β€² and π‘₯β€² = π‘₯ for each π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋, and
not relevant). It can be shown that (𝐢, 𝑓 ) is an argument               β€’ let the set of rules be composed of πœ‘ ←
of the resulting ABA framework iff πœ‘ is satisfiable.                       𝑐1 , . . . , π‘π‘š , and 𝑐𝑖 ← 𝑧 with 𝑧 = π‘₯ and π‘₯ ∈ 𝑐𝑖
                                                                           or 𝑧 = π‘₯β€² and Β¬π‘₯ ∈ 𝑐𝑖 .
   We want to emphasize that this result does not imply
that it is harder to compute the core compared to a corre-             The resulting ABA framework is bounded by 2-
sponding AF, since one can directly extract the core from           derivation-depth as each proof tree has height at most
the corresponding AF. Rather, Proposition 13 formalizes             2. We observe that the presented reduction formalizes our
that skipping computation of the proof trees in order to            introductory example:
construct the core is a hard task in general.
   From now on, we restrict our attention to cores, and         Example 15. Given the CNF-formula πœ‘ = (π‘₯1 ∨ Β¬π‘₯2 ) ∧
assume that, for a given ABA, we operate exclusively on         (Β¬π‘₯1 ∨π‘₯2 ) from the introduction. Following Reduction 14,
a core, unless explicitly mentioned otherwise.                  we obtain an ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) which
                                                                contains the assumptions π’œ = {π‘₯1 , π‘₯2 , π‘₯β€²1 , π‘₯β€²2 } and the
                                                                rules πœ™ ← 𝑐1 , 𝑐2 and
4. Bounds on Assumption-based                                            β€’ 𝑐1 ← π‘₯1 , 𝑐1 ← π‘₯β€²2 (since π‘₯1 , Β¬π‘₯2 ∈ 𝑐1 ) as well
   Frameworks                                                              as
                                                                         β€’ 𝑐2 ← π‘₯β€²1 , 𝑐2 ← π‘₯2 (since π‘₯β€²1 , π‘₯2 ∈ 𝑐2 )
In this section we study the impact of bounding certain
parts of the input ABA on the complexity of reasoning               Moreover, the ABA framework assigns symmetric con-
and size of cores (and corresponding AFs in cases). We              traries, i.e., π‘₯𝑖 = π‘₯′𝑖 and π‘₯′𝑖 = π‘₯𝑖 for 𝑖 ∈ {1, 2}. The
consider bounds on derivation-depth and bodies of rules.            resulting framework indeed coincides with the introduc-
   When investigating size of cores, we make use of the             tory example (cf. Example 9).
following definition. Given an ABA 𝐷 the size of 𝐷 (|𝐷|)
is the length of a (direct) string representation of 𝐷. Let            It can be shown that the special atom πœ‘ is credulously
π’Ÿ be a set of ABA frameworks. We say that the cores of              accepted under admissible semantics in the ABA frame-
π’Ÿ are polynomially bounded if there is a polynomial 𝑝 s.t.          work iff the formula πœ‘ is satisfiable.
𝑝(|𝐷|) β‰₯ |A| for all 𝐷 ∈ π’Ÿ with 𝐹 = (A, R) the core of                 Observe that tree-based arguments in the correspond-
𝐷. We will see below that the cores of the set of all ABA           ing AF in Reduction 14 have derivation-depth of at most
frameworks are not polynomially bounded.                            2. We obtain that credulous reasoning is NP -complete




                                                               96
οΏ½         πœ‘             πœ‘              πœ‘           πœ‘           Proposition 18. Credulous reasoning under admissibility
        𝑐1 𝑐2        𝑐1 𝑐2       𝑐1 𝑐2          𝑐1 𝑐2         is decidable in polynomial time in cores of symmetric
                                                              ABAs.
       π‘₯1 π‘₯β€²1        π‘₯β€²2 π‘₯β€²1     π‘₯1 π‘₯2          π‘₯β€²2 π‘₯2

                                                              4.2. Size of the Constructed AF
                π‘₯1         π‘₯β€²1   π‘₯2       π‘₯β€²2
                                                           From identifying arguments as pairs of assumption sets
         𝑐2            𝑐1         𝑐1             𝑐2        and claims we directly obtain that the number of argu-
          π‘₯β€²1         π‘₯1          π‘₯ β€²
                                               π‘₯2          ments in cores is bounded by 2|π’œ| Β· |β„’ βˆ– π’œ| + |π’œ| for
                                    2
                                                           each ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ). We establish a
Figure 1: AF instantiation of the ABA framework from bound on the number of tree-based arguments that consid-
Example 15 for the formula πœ‘ = (π‘₯1 ∨ Β¬π‘₯2 ) ∧ (Β¬π‘₯1 ∨ π‘₯2 ) ers derivation-depth and rule-size and show that bound-
(cf. Reduction 14).                                        ing both derivation-depth and rule-size yields ABAs with
                                                           polynomially bounded cores.
                                                              The number of tree-based arguments that can be con-
even when restricting ABA frameworks to be bounded by structed from a given ABA framework 𝐷 depends on the
π‘˜-derivation-depth for some constant π‘˜ β‰₯ 2. Moreover, number of rules, derivation-depth, rule-size, and number
in general Reduction 14 yields cores which are not poly- of rules with same heads, as follows.
nomially bounded by the given ABA framework: for a
                                                           Theorem 19. For each π‘š-derivation-depth and π‘˜-rule-
formula πœ™ with π‘š clauses and π‘˜ variables per clause, we
                  π‘š                                        size bounded ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) with
construct up to π‘˜ many arguments with conclusion πœ™.
                                                           |{π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› | β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) = 𝑠}| ≀ 𝑙 for all 𝑠 ∈ β„’, there are at
Figure 1 depicts the core (equivalent to the corresponding
                                                           mostβˆ‘οΈ€π‘™π‘ Β· |β„’ βˆ– π’œ| + |π’œ| many tree-based arguments with
AF) of the constructed ABA framework from Example 15.              π‘šβˆ’1 𝑖
                                                           𝑝 =     𝑖=0 π‘˜ .
Here, we have 22 many arguments with conclusion πœ™.
   A slight adaption of the reduction shows that credu- Proof. To prove the statement, we show that the number
lous reasoning under admissibility remains NP -complete, of all possible trees constructible from 𝐷 is bounded by
when bounding instead the body-size of the rules by 2.     𝑛 Β· 𝑙𝑝 with 𝑝 = π‘šβˆ’1 π‘˜π‘– and 𝑛 = |β„’ βˆ– π’œ|. Here, we
                                                                             βˆ‘οΈ€
                                                                                 𝑖=0

Theorem 16. Credulous reasoning under admissibility       do not require that the leaves of the trees are labelled as
remains NP-hard even if restricted to derivation-depth    assumptions. Observe that the set of all tree-based argu-
bounded or rule-size bounded ABA frameworks.              ments is a subset of the number of all trees constructible
                                                          from 𝐷.
   A closer inspection of the ABAs constructed from Re-      For each literal 𝑠 ∈ β„’ βˆ– π’œ which appears as head of
duction 14 points to another class of ABA frameworks a rule in 𝐷, there are at most 𝑙 Β· π‘₯π‘˜ many trees where
with notable properties. In this reduction, we construct π‘₯ is the maximum number of trees with head 𝑐 for a
ABA frameworks with a symmetric contrary function, i.e., literal 𝑐 ∈ π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) for some rule π‘Ÿ with β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(𝑠). Indeed,
π‘Ž = 𝑏 iff 𝑏 = π‘Ž for all π‘Ž, 𝑏 ∈ π’œ. We call these ABA there are at most 𝑙 rules with head 𝑠, all bounded by π‘˜. We
frameworks symmetric. First, observe that credulous rea- express this correspondence via the function 𝑓 (π‘₯) = 𝑙·π‘₯π‘˜ .
soning in this framework is NP -hard (following directly The total number of trees with root 𝑠 constructible from
from Theorem 16).                                         𝐷 after π‘š steps is thus given by 𝑓 π‘š (1). We show that
                                                                     βˆ‘οΈ€π‘šβˆ’1 𝑖
                                                          𝑓 π‘š (1) = 𝑙 𝑖=0 π‘˜ via induction over π‘š.
Corollary 17. Credulous reasoning under admissibility
                                                             For π‘š = 1, we have 𝑓 (1) = 𝑙.
is NP -hard for symmetric ABA frameworks.
                                                             Now assume the statement holds true for rule depth
   On the other hand, we observe that the computational π‘š βˆ’ 1.
hardness in symmetric ABAs stems entirely from the con-
struction of arguments: indeed, constructing the cores                    𝑓 π‘š (1) = 𝑙 Β· (𝑓 π‘šβˆ’1 (1))π‘˜
                                                                                          βˆ‘οΈ€π‘šβˆ’2 𝑖
results in AFs with |π’œ|/2 many even cycles of length 2 (a                         = 𝑙 Β· (𝑙 𝑖=0 π‘˜ )π‘˜
cycle for every assumption and its negation) satisfying                                    βˆ‘οΈ€π‘šβˆ’2 𝑖
that all arguments with claim 𝑠 ∈/ π’œ have only incoming                           = 𝑙 Β· π‘™π‘˜( 𝑖=0 π‘˜ )
attacks. For an example we refer to Figure 1. Credulous                              βˆ‘οΈ€π‘šβˆ’1 𝑖

reasoning under admissibility in such AFs is decidable                            = 𝑙 𝑖=0 π‘˜ .
in time polynomial in the number of arguments, since it
                                                          We thus obtain that the number of all possible trees
suffices to check if there exists an argument having the
                                                          constructible from 𝐷 is bounded by 𝑙𝑝 Β· 𝑛 with 𝑝 =
queried claim that is not attacked by both arguments in a βˆ‘οΈ€π‘šβˆ’1 𝑖
                                                             𝑖=0 π‘˜ .
2-cycle.




                                                         97
οΏ½   Intuitively, exponentiality of the number of tree-based      new argument. Therefore, after at most |A| + 1 iterations
arguments stems from 𝑝, and thus from derivation-depth          we are done. Each iteration visits |β„›| rules. Consider one
and rule-size. Moreover, it is clear that the result extends    particular rule π‘Ÿ. For each body literal, we need to search
to the number of arguments in the cores of derivation-          through at most |A| arguments. Since |π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ)| ≀ π‘˜,
depth and rule-size bounded ABA frameworks. Bounding            this is in π’ͺ(|A|π‘˜ ). In order to decide whether or not the
both parameters thus yields polynomially bounded cores.         induced argument 𝐴 ⊒ β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) needs to be added, we
                                                                again search through the at most |A| already constructed
Corollary 20. The cores of the set of ABA frameworks            arguments and compare. In summary, we visit rules at
which are both derivation-depth and rule-size bounded by        most (|A| + 1) Β· |β„›| times and thereby, we can perform
some constant π‘˜ are polynomially bounded.                       the necessary computations in time in 1π’ͺ(|A|π‘˜+1 ).
  Bounding derivation-depth or rule-size individually,
                                                          The preceding result together with Corollary 20 yields
however, does not yield cores that are polynomially
                                                        a procedure to obtain a polynomially bounded core in
bounded.
                                                        polynomial time for rule-size bounded and derivation-
Proposition 21. The cores of ABA frameworks which depth bounded ABA frameworks.
are derivation-depth bounded by some constant π‘˜ are not
                                                        Corollary 23. The cores of the set of rule-size and
polynomially bounded. Likewise, the cores of rule-size
                                                        derivation-depth bounded ABA frameworks can be com-
bounded ABA frameworks are not polynomially bounded.
                                                        puted in polynomial time in size of the given ABA frame-
                                                        work.
4.3. Computation of the Core
                                                                   We remark that it is currently not known whether the
As the reader might have noticed, having polynomially           condition of rule-size boundedness in Theorem 22 can
bounded cores does not (directly) imply the existence of        be dropped; we conjecture that the condition is required.
a polynomial-time algorithm that can actually obtain the        In any case, Theorem 22 also yields the result that enu-
core in question. We show that for ABA frameworks               merating arguments in the core of a rule-size bounded
which are rule-size bounded an algorithm can be ob-             ABA framework has incremental polynomial time com-
tained that enumerates arguments in polynomial-time re-         plexity [19], i.e., one can in polynomial time w.r.t. the
garding size of input and number of arguments. This             given ABA and partially enumerated arguments find a
can be achieved by a direct algorithm: for each rule            fresh argument or conclude that all arguments were enu-
π‘Ÿ with π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) = {𝑠1 , . . . , 𝑠𝑛 } and already computed        merated.
(tree-based) arguments {𝛼1 , . . . , π›Όπ‘š } loop through each
𝑛-sized subset 𝑋 of {𝛼1 , . . . , π›Όπ‘š } and check whether
cl (𝑋) = π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ). If so, attach it to a potential new argu-     5. Transformations and
ment concluding β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ). If this argument is fresh, add            Complexity Trade-offs
it to the output. If 𝑛 ≀ π‘˜ for a constant π‘˜, this search is
bounded polynomially by the given ABA and size of core.   We saw that ABA frameworks may yield a core not poly-
Theorem 22. The cores of ABA frameworks whose rule- nomially bounded, but with polynomial-time reasoning
size is bounded by a constant can be constructed in poly- (under the credulous view and admissibility), e.g., when
nomial time w.r.t. the size of the given ABA and core.    looking at Reduction 14. In this section we look at possi-
                                                          bility results and an impossibility result of transforming
Proof. Consider the following brute-force procedure.      a given ABA to another ABA framework whose core is
                                                          polynomially bounded or allows for polynomial-time rea-
      β€’ loop through each rule π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› as long as new soning.
         arguments are added.
            – given π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) = {π‘Ž1 , . . . , π‘Žπ‘‘ }, for each      5.1. Tractable Reasoning in Core
              subset π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑑 of the already con-
              structed arguments s.t. cl (π‘₯𝑖 ) = π‘Žπ‘–        Recall that one of our main goals was to formalize the
                                                           idea that one could construct ABA frameworks in a way
                 * if the corresponding argument 𝐴 ⊒
                    β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) is not yet constructed, add it that the induced AF might be large, but yields tractable
                    to the list;                           reasoning in return. As we already mentioned, the ABA
                                                           framework constructed in the motivating example corre-
                 * otherwise break;
                                                           sponds to applying Reduction 14. Our intuition is that the
By definition, this algorithm constructs the correct argu- ABA frameworks constructed according to this reduction
ments in 𝐹 . The outer loop over each rule can be left indeed yield AFs with tractable reasoning (though in the
once there was one iteration which did not induce any potential exponential size of the AF). This intuition can




                                                           98
οΏ½be confirmed as follows: First, observe hat Reduction 14             The transformation is defined as follows. Intuitively, for
yields symmetric ABA frameworks (by definition). Thus             each conclusion 𝑠 derivable from a given ABA framework
by Proposition 18 stating that reasoning in symmetric AFs         𝐷, we introduce fresh assumptions 𝑠𝑑 (’𝑠 is derivable’)
is indeed tractable, we obtain the desired outcome.               and 𝑠𝑛𝑑 (’𝑠 is not derivable’) that simulate derivations.
   However, this only states that a certain class of ABA          The resulting ABA framework 𝐷′ contains only rules
frameworks possesses this property. We would like to go           with assumptions in the body, each of which gives rise
one step further and transform an arbitrary given ABA             to exactly one tree-based argument. Since no rule in 𝐷′
framework s.t. the corresponding AF behaves this way. It          contains non-assumptions, each proof tree is of height 1.
turns out that this can be achieved indeed, at least if we
                                                                  Definition 26. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be a non-circular
restrict our attention to some target conclusion, say π‘₯ ∈ β„’.
                                                                  ABA framework such that each 𝑠 ∈ β„’ is in Th 𝐷 (π’œ). We
The underlying idea is surprisingly simple: Suppose we
                                                                  define 𝐷′ = (β„’β€² , β„›β€² , π’œβ€² , β€² ) as the AF-sensitive ABA
want to transform the ABA framework 𝐷. Since the SAT
                                                                  framework of 𝐷 as follows. For each 𝑠 ∈ β„’ βˆ– π’œ
problem is NP-complete, we can in polynomial time con-
struct a formula πœ‘ which is satisfiable iff π‘₯ is credulously           β€’ let 𝑠𝑑 and 𝑠𝑛𝑑 be two fresh assumptions, with
accepted in 𝐷. Now, our Reduction 14 translates πœ‘ into                 β€’ 𝑠𝑑 = 𝑠𝑛𝑑 and 𝑠𝑛𝑑 = 𝑠 in β€² .
an ABA framework with the behavior we wish to obtain.
All these steps can be performed in polynomial time. ThisLet π’œβ€² = π’œ βˆͺ {𝑠𝑑 , 𝑠𝑛𝑑 | 𝑠 ∈ β„’ βˆ– π’œ} and β„’β€² = β„’ βˆͺ π’œβ€² .
yields the following main theorem.                       Contraries in 𝐷′ are defined as for 𝐷, except for the
                                                         new assumptions as above. For each rule π‘Ÿ ∈ β„›, let π‘Ÿβ€²
Theorem 24. For each ABA framework 𝐷 = being π‘Ÿ except that if π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) contains a non-assumption
(β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) and π‘₯ ∈ β„’ one can construct an ABA frame- 𝑠, replace 𝑠 by 𝑠𝑑 . Finally, set β„›β€² = {π‘Ÿβ€² | π‘Ÿ ∈ β„›}.
work 𝐷′ in polynomial time s.t.
                                                           Let us consider an example.
     β€’ under admissibility, π‘₯ is credulously accepted in
       𝐷 iff π‘₯ is credulously accepted in 𝐷′ ,           Example 27. Consider an ABA framework 𝐷 =
                                                         (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) with assumptions π’œ = {π‘Ž, 𝑏}, rules β„›:
     β€’ reasoning in the corresponding AF 𝐹 is tractable
       in the size of 𝐹 .                                       π‘Ÿ1 : 𝑝 ← π‘ž; π‘Ÿ2 : π‘ž ← π‘Ž; π‘Ÿ3 : 𝑠 ← 𝑏;
   We want to mention however that this procedure as              and contraries π‘Ž = π‘Ÿ and 𝑏 = 𝑝. In 𝐷, both {π‘Ž} and {𝑏}
given above is rather theoretical. We believe that finding        are admissible as they symmetrically attack each other.
a constructive proof for this result is an exciting future          Following Definition 26, we obtain the corresponding
work direction.                                                   ABA 𝐷′ = (β„’β€² , β„›β€² , π’œβ€² , β€² ) with assumptions π‘Ž, 𝑏, and
                                                                  additional assumptions 𝑝𝑑 , 𝑝𝑛𝑑 , π‘žπ‘‘ , π‘žπ‘›π‘‘ , 𝑠𝑑 , 𝑠𝑛𝑑 ; and
5.2. Obtaining a Polynomial Core                                  rules β„›β€² :

Now we turn our attention to the opposite direction: We                  π‘Ÿ1β€² : 𝑝 ← π‘žπ‘‘ ;   π‘Ÿ2β€² : π‘ž ← π‘Ž;    π‘Ÿ3β€² : 𝑠 ← 𝑏.
present a general polynomial-time procedure which under
mild conditions transforms a given ABA framework 𝐷 s.t.           The assumption π‘žπ‘‘ is defended by each assumption set
(i) the translated framework is equivalent under projection       that derives π‘ž (since π‘žπ‘‘ is attacked by π‘žπ‘›π‘‘ which is in
to 𝐷 and (ii) the core of the translated ABA framework            turn attacked by all assumption sets that derive π‘ž). Conse-
is polynomially bounded. That is, this time we do not try         quently, {π‘žπ‘‘ , π‘Ž} is admissible since it derives π‘ž and 𝑝 and
to obtain an AF with tractable reasoning, but we wish to          thus defeats the attackers 𝑏 and π‘žπ‘›π‘‘ . Likewise, {𝑏, π‘žπ‘›π‘‘ }
prevent the exponential blow-up which might be caused             is admissible in 𝐷′ as it defends itself against the attack
from the instantiation procedure.                                 from π‘žπ‘‘ and π‘Ž.
   We take the definition of circular tree-based arguments     As we have seen in the above example, restricting the
(proof trees) from Craven and Toni (2016).                   outcome to the initial set of assumptions yields the original
                                                             extensions. This is not a coincidence, as we show next:
Definition 25. A tree-based argument is circular if there
                                                             admissible assumption sets and derivations are preserved
is a path from a leaf to the root which contains two dis-
                                                             when projecting to π’œ of the original ABA framework.
tinct vertices with the same label. An ABA framework is
circular if there is a circular tree-based argument for this Proposition 28. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be a non-circular
framework.                                                   ABA framework such that each 𝑠 ∈ β„’ is in Th 𝐷 (π’œ) and
                                                             𝐷′ the AF-sensitive ABA framework of 𝐷. It holds that
   We remark that ABA frameworks obtained from Re-
duction 14 are non-circular and all atoms are derivable           β€’ if 𝐸 ∈ adm(𝐷), then there is an 𝐸 β€² ∈ adm(𝐷′ )
(independently of whether the underlying formula is satis-          with 𝐸 = 𝐸 β€² βˆ©π’œ and Th β„› (𝐸) = Th β„›β€² (𝐸 β€² )βˆ©β„’,
fiable).                                                            and




                                                             99
οΏ½                                πœ‘                                   β€’ if 𝐸 ∈ adm(𝐷), then there is an 𝐸 β€² ∈ adm(𝐷′ )
                          (𝑐1 )𝑑 (𝑐2 )𝑑                               with 𝐸 = 𝐸 β€² βˆ©π’œ and Th β„› (𝐸) = Th β„›β€² (𝐸 β€² )βˆ©β„’,
                                                                    β€’ if 𝐸 β€² ∈ adm(𝐷′ ), then 𝐸 β€² ∩ π’œ ∈ adm(𝐷) and
                                                                      Th β„› (𝐸) βŠ‡ Th β„›β€² (𝐸 β€² ) ∩ β„’, and
      (𝑐1 )𝑑          (𝑐1 )𝑛𝑑       (𝑐2 )𝑛𝑑         (𝑐2 )𝑑
                                                                    β€’ the size of the AF corresponding to 𝐷′ is bounded
                                                                      by 𝑝(|𝐷′ |).

                𝑐2         𝑐1       𝑐1        𝑐2
                                                               5.3. Trade-Off: Size and Complexity
                π‘₯β€²1       π‘₯1        π‘₯β€²2       π‘₯2
                                                            In Section 5.1 the central idea was to start off with Reduc-
                π‘₯1        π‘₯β€²1       π‘₯2        π‘₯β€²2           tion 14 modeling a CNF-formula. We could try to do the
                                                            same here and then apply Theorem 31 in order to avoid
Figure 2: Constructed ABA framework from Example 15 the exponential blow-up in size of the AF. However, if we
when applying the construction from Definition 26.          could proceed like this with one-to-one correspondence
                                                            of the semantics, we would end up solving an NP-hard
                                                            problem in polynomial time. Therefore, the condition of
      β€’ if 𝐸 ∈ adm(𝐷 ), then 𝐸 = 𝐸 ∩ π’œ ∈ adm(𝐷) equivalence under projection in Theorem 31 seems neces-
             β€²            β€²               β€²

        and Th β„› (𝐸) βŠ‡ Th β„›β€² (𝐸 β€² ) ∩ β„’.                    sary. We present an impossibility result stating that one
                                                            cannot transform a given ABA framework to an equiva-
   We note that Th β„› (𝐸) and Th β„›β€² (𝐸 β€² )βˆ©β„’ are not equal lent one with polynomially bounded cores and bounded
but in subset-relation in the second bullet since deriva- rule-size, at least under standard complexity-theoretic as-
tions are potentially cut off in the construction of an AF- sumptions.
sensitive ABA framework. Consider the ABA frameworks
𝐷 and 𝐷′ in Example 27. In 𝐷, the assumption π‘Ž derives Theorem 32. Assuming 𝑃 ΜΈ= NP , there is no constant π‘˜
𝑝 and π‘ž while in 𝐷′ , the assumption π‘Ž derives only π‘ž. Thus and polynomial-time algorithm which translates a given
Th β„› ({π‘Ž}) = {π‘Ž, 𝑝, π‘ž} βŠ‡ {π‘Ž, π‘ž} = Th β„›β€² ({π‘Ž})(βˆ©β„’).          ABA framework 𝐷 to another ABA framework 𝐷′ s.t.
   From the construction of AF-sensitive frameworks, it
                                                                  β€’ adm(𝐷) = adm(𝐷′ ),
follows that the cores are polynomially bounded. Indeed,
                                                                  β€’ Th β„› (𝐸) = Th β„›β€² (𝐸) for 𝐸 ∈ adm(𝐷),
since each assumption as well as each rule corresponds
to precisely one tree-based argument, we obtain that the          β€’ 𝐷′ has rule-size bounded by π‘˜, and
                                   β€²     β€²
corresponding AF has at most |π’œ |+|β„› | many arguments             β€’ the cores of the set of ABA frameworks π’Ÿβ€² trans-
in the core.                                                        lated by the algorithm are bounded polynomially.

Proposition 29. Let π’Ÿ be the set of all non-circular ABA       Proof. Suppose that such an algorithm 𝑇 exists. Let
frameworks with all atoms derivable, and π’Ÿβ€² the set of         πœ‘ = 𝑐1 ∧ Β· Β· Β· ∧ π‘π‘š be a Boolean formula in CNF over
AF-sensitive ABA frameworks from π’Ÿ. It holds that the          clauses 𝐢 = {𝑐1 , . . . , π‘π‘š } and Boolean variables 𝑋 =
cores of π’Ÿβ€² are polynomially bounded.                          {π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 }. Let 𝐷 be the ABA framework obtained
                                                               from Reduction 14, and let 𝐷′ = 𝑇 (𝐷) be the outcome
Example 30. Let us consider again our ABA framework            of the algorithm. Note that 𝐷′ can be constructed in time
from Example 15. Applying the above construction, we           polynomial w.r.t. size of πœ‘. By Reduction 14 and second
obtain an ABA 𝐷′ with additional assumptions (𝑐1 )𝑑 ,          item, it holds that πœ‘ is satisfiable iff there is an admissible
(𝑐1 )𝑛𝑑 , (𝑐2 )𝑑 , (𝑐2 )𝑛𝑑 ; moreover, we replace rule πœ™ ←     assumption set 𝐴 with πœ‘ ∈ Th β„›β€² (𝐴).
𝑐1 , 𝑐2 with the rule πœ™ ← (𝑐1 )𝑑 , (𝑐2 )𝑑 . The resulting AF      Each admissible assumption-set 𝐡 in 𝐷 satisfies 𝐡 βŠ†
is given in Figure 2.                                          𝑋 βˆͺ {π‘₯β€² | π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋}, moreover, 𝐡 does not contain both
                                                               π‘₯ and π‘₯β€² for any π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 Also note that each conflict-free
   We can now gather our results to infer our desired theo-    assumption-set is admissible since Reduction 14 yields a
rem. Due to Proposition 29 the AF-sensitive ABA frame-         symmetric ABA framework.
work induces an AF with polynomial size and Proposi-              By the first item, 𝐷′ has the same admissible assump-
tion 28 ensures that applying this constructions preserves     tion sets as 𝐷′ . It holds that there is an argument (𝐡, πœ‘) in
admissible reasoning under projection. Combining these         𝐷′ and 𝐡 does not contain both π‘₯ and π‘₯β€² for any π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋
insights yields the following central result.                  iff πœ‘ is credulously accepted under admissible semantics
                                                               in 𝐷′ iff πœ‘ is credulously accepted under admissible se-
Theorem 31. There is some polynomial 𝑝 such that each
                                                               mantics in 𝐷 iff πœ‘ is satisfiable. Thus, if one finds an
non-circular ABA framework 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) with
                                                               argument (𝐡, πœ‘) for 𝐷′ without β€œcomplementary literals”
β„’ βŠ† Th 𝐷 (π’œ) can be transformed in polynomial time
                                                               (i.e., without any π‘₯ ∈ 𝑋 s.t. both π‘₯ and π‘₯β€² are in 𝐡) we
into an ABA framework 𝐷′ where




                                                             100
οΏ½conclude that πœ‘ is satisfiable, and if πœ‘ is unsatisfiable no   Proof. Suppose there is a cycle in 𝐹 . Then there is also a
such argument in 𝐷′ exists.                                    cycle π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 in 𝐹 where cl (π‘₯𝑖 ) ΜΈ= cl (π‘₯𝑗 ) for 𝑖 ΜΈ= 𝑗
   By Theorem 22 and due to the third item, one can enu-       which can be seen as follows. If cl (π‘₯𝑖 ) = cl (π‘₯𝑗 ), then
merate all arguments of 𝐷′ in polynomial time. Overall,        (supposing 𝑖 < 𝑗) there is an attack from π‘₯𝑖 to π‘₯𝑗+1
we can search the space of all arguments in 𝐷′ in time         and we can simply remove the sub-sequence consisting
polynomial to size of πœ‘, implying that we can decide           of π‘₯𝑖+1 , . . . π‘₯𝑗 . This procedure can be iterated until we
satisfiability of πœ‘ in polynomial time, a contradiction to     obtain the sub-sequence with the two required properties.
𝑃 ΜΈ= NP .                                                          We now prove the two statements. i) By iteratively
                                                               applying Lemma 35 we find a cycle in G𝐷 . ii) By utilizing
                                                               cl (π‘₯𝑖 ) ΜΈ= cl (π‘₯𝑗 ) for 𝑖 ΜΈ= 𝑗, Lemma 35 even guarantees
6. Dependency Graphs on ABA                                    that the length is preserved which yields an odd cycle in
                                                               G𝐷 if π‘₯1 , . . . , π‘₯𝑛 is odd.
We look at dependencies induced by the rules of a given
ABA framework, inspired by dependency graphs in logic  The above proposition does not hold for even cycles.
programming, and related but different to the dependency
                                                    As a counter-example consider the even-cycle free de-
graph notion existing for ABA [17].                 pendency graph of Example 34. In contrast, the core 𝐹
Definition 33. The dependency graph G𝐷 = (𝑉, 𝐸, 𝑙) possesses an even cycle. Vice versa, given a cycle in the
for a given ABA 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) is an edge-labelled dependency graph, we can construct a cycle of the same
graph with                                          length in 𝐹 .

     β€’ 𝑉 = β„’ is the set of vertices,                           Proposition 37. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
     β€’ edge 𝑒 = (𝑠, 𝑑) ∈ 𝐸 iff i) there is some rule           work such that each 𝑠 ∈ β„’ is in Th(π’œ), 𝐹 be the core
       π‘Ÿ ∈ β„› with 𝑠 ∈ π‘π‘œπ‘‘π‘¦(π‘Ÿ) and β„Žπ‘’π‘Žπ‘‘(π‘Ÿ) = {𝑑}, in            and G𝐷 the dependency graph. If 𝑝1 , . . . , 𝑝𝑛 is a cycle
       this case 𝑙(𝑒) = +; or ii) 𝑑 ∈ π’œ and 𝑑 = 𝑠, in this     in G𝐷 , then there is a cycle of the same length in 𝐹 .
       case, 𝑙(𝑒) = βˆ’.
                                                         Proof. For 2 ≀ 𝑖 ≀ 𝑛 let 𝑝𝑖 be an assumption. By con-
  In brief, vertices represent atoms, and positive edges struction of G𝐷 , π‘π‘–βˆ’1 = 𝑝𝑖 . Since 𝐷 is trim, there is
connect body elements and heads of rules, while negative an argument π‘₯1 with conclusion cl (π‘₯1 ) = π‘π‘–βˆ’1 . Now
edges correspond to contraries.                          let 𝑗 be minimal s.t. 𝑖 < 𝑗 and 𝑝𝑗 is an assumption.
                                                         Again since 𝐷 is trim, there is also an argument π‘₯2 with
Example 34. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
                                                         cl (π‘₯2 ) = π‘π‘—βˆ’1 = 𝑝𝑗 . Observe that π‘₯2 is attacked by
work with π’œ = {π‘Ž, 𝑏, 𝑐, 𝑑, 𝑒}, distinct contraries π‘₯ = π‘₯
                                                       Β―
                                                         arguments with conclusion π‘π‘–βˆ’1 . Thus, we have an at-
for each π‘₯ ∈ π’œ and the following rules:
                                                         tack from π‘₯1 to , π‘₯2 in 𝐹 . In G𝐷 , the length of the path
              Β―β†π‘Ž
              𝑑             ¯𝑏 ← π‘Ž         ¯𝑐 ← 𝑏        π‘π‘–βˆ’1 , . . . π‘π‘—βˆ’1 equals one since by choice of 𝑗 we have
                                                         {π‘π‘–βˆ’1 , . . . π‘π‘—βˆ’1 }βˆ©π’œ = {𝑝𝑖 }. If we continue analogously
              ¯←𝑐
              π‘Ž             ¯𝑒 ← 𝑑         ¯←𝑒
                                           π‘Ž
                                                         we find a cycle in 𝐹 having the same length as our cycle
Then the dependency graph G𝐷 is given as follows.        𝑝1 , . . . , 𝑝 𝑛 .

              βˆ’        +             +        βˆ’                  The dependency graph can be utilized to obtain approx-
         𝑑        Β―
                  𝑑          π‘Ž           ¯𝑏       𝑏            imations for several bounds we considered throughout this
     +                           βˆ’                     +       paper.
         ¯𝑒       𝑒          π‘Ž
                             Β―           𝑐        ¯𝑐
              βˆ’        +             +        βˆ’            Proposition 38. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA frame-
                                                           work and G𝐷 = (𝑉, 𝐸, 𝑙) the dependency graph. i) For
   A path (cycle) in G𝐷 is defined as usual; the length of the rule size π‘˜ of 𝐷 we have π‘˜ ≀ maxπ‘’βˆˆπ‘‰ |{𝑒′ ∈ 𝑉 |
a path (cycle) is the number of edges labeled β€œβˆ’β€. The (𝑒′ , 𝑒) ∈ 𝐸}|. ii) If G𝐷 is acyclic, then the derivation-
relation between paths in G𝐷 and the core 𝐹 of 𝐷 is very depth of 𝐷 is bounded by the size of the longest path
close as formalized in the following lemma.                (counting β€œ+” labels) in G𝐷 .
Lemma 35. Let 𝐷 be an ABA framework with core 𝐹 =                 Finally, we get a tighter approximation for the size of
(A, R) and dependency graph G𝐷 . If (𝛼, 𝛽) ∈ R, then           the core than our previously established term 2|π’œ| Β·|β„’βˆ–π’œ|.
there is a path of length one from cl (𝛼) to cl (𝛽) in G𝐷 .
                                                            Proposition 39. Let 𝐷 = (β„’, β„›, π’œ, ) be an ABA
   The observation can be extended to the following result. framework, 𝐹 = (A, R) be the core and G𝐷 the de-
Proposition 36. Let 𝐷 be an ABA framework with core pendency graph. For each 𝑠 ∈ β„’ let 𝑝(𝑠) = {π‘Ž ∈
𝐹 and dependency graph G𝐷 . i) If G𝐷 is acyclic, then so π’œ  βˆ‘οΈ€ | π‘Ž has|𝑝(𝑠)|
                                                                        a path in G𝐷 to 𝑠}. Then |A| ≀ |π’œ| +
is 𝐹 . ii) If G𝐷 is odd-cycle free, then so is 𝐹 .             π‘ βˆˆβ„’βˆ–π΄ 2       .




                                                           101
οΏ½7. Discussion                                                    Acknowledgments

The computation of a corresponding AF, and different             We thank the anonymous reviewers of this paper for their
forms of representing arguments together with optimiza-          helpful comments. This research was funded in whole, or
tions for structured argumentation have been consid-             in part, by the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) W1255-N23,
ered before, e.g., for ABA [17, 20, 13], and for other           by the Vienna Science and Technology Fund (WWTF)
forms of structured argumentation [12, 21]. Moreover,            through project ICT19-065, and by the German Federal
complexity of ABA was investigated in several direc-             Ministry of Education and Research (BMBF, 01/S18026A-
tions [22, 23, 24, 25], potentially exponential AFs arising      F) by funding the competence center for Big Data and AI
from structured argumentation and their issues was dis-          β€œScaDS.AI” Dresden/Leipzig.
cussed, e.g., by Strass et al. (2019), and infinite arguments
for ABA were investigated [27]. In contrast to these works,
we relate features of the given ABA instance to the size
                                                                 References
of the resulting arguments and complexity of reasoning.           [1] P. Baroni, D. Gabbay, M. Giacomin, L. van der
We focused on arguments as pair structures (assumptions               Torre (Eds.), Handbook of Formal Argumentation,
and claim).                                                           College Publications, 2018.
   Considering variants for representing arguments is an          [2] K. Atkinson, P. Baroni, M. Giacomin, A. Hunter,
appealing avenue for future work, but it seems that differ-           H. Prakken, C. Reed, G. R. Simari, M. Thimm,
ent representations arrive at other computational barriers.           S. Villata, Towards artificial argumentation, AI
For instance, Lehtonen et al. (2017) showed #P-hardness               Magazine 38 (2017) 25–36.
under subtractive reductions for counting the number of           [3] A. Bondarenko, P. M. Dung, R. A. Kowalski, F. Toni,
argument structures for a representation incorporating a              An abstract, argumentation-theoretic approach to
form of minimality on the assumption sets. When requir-               default reasoning, Artif. Intell. 93 (1997) 63–101.
ing a core to contain only arguments with subset-minimal          [4] S. Modgil, H. Prakken, A general account of argu-
assumption sets one can show hardness for argument con-               mentation with preferences, Artif. Intell. 195 (2013)
struction, e.g., it is NP -hard to decide whether there is a          361–397.
subset-minimal argument not yet constructed.                      [5] A. J. GarcΓ­a, G. R. Simari, Defeasible logic pro-
   Our results on trade-offs regarding size and complex-              gramming: An argumentative approach, Theory
ity of reasoning suggest that it might be worthwhile to               Pract. Log. Program. 4 (2004) 95–138.
pre-process ABA frameworks in a suitable way before               [6] P. Besnard, A. Hunter, Elements of Argumentation,
utilizing AF solvers; also, one may model problems in                 MIT Press, 2008.
ABA such that the corresponding AF is either small in             [7] P. M. Dung, On the acceptability of arguments and
size or the reasoning in the AF is tractable, depending on            its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning,
the intention.                                                        logic programming and n-person games, Artif. Intell.
   The most interesting future work directions we identify            77 (1995) 321–358.
are as follows. First, the results which make use of the          [8] K. Čyras, X. Fan, C. Schulz, F. Toni, Assumption-
actual semantics are only phrased for admissible sets yet.            based argumentation: Disputes, explanations, pref-
In particular generalizing Theorem 31 to the other clas-              erences, in: P. Baroni, D. Gabbay, M. Giacomin,
sical Dung semantics would contribute to our research.                L. van der Torre (Eds.), Handbook of Formal Argu-
Moreover, Theorem 24 is not constructive and one needs                mentation, College Publications, 2018, pp. 365–408.
to fix a given atom in advance. Finding an analogous              [9] R. Craven, F. Toni, C. Cadar, A. Hadad,
construction which preserves the semantics, similar in                M. Williams, Efficient argumentation for medical
spirit to Theorem 31, would be a great generalization. Fur-           decision-making, in: Proc. KR, AAAI Press, 2012,
thermore, it would be interesting to investigate to which             pp. 598–602.
extent a pre-processing as suggested by Theorem 31 can           [10] K. Čyras, T. Oliveira, A. Karamlou, F. Toni,
help boosting the performance of ABA solvers. As a final              Assumption-based argumentation with preferences
remark we want to mention that many other structured for-             and goals for patient-centric reasoning with inter-
malisms are similar in their spirit, i.e. induce a potentially        acting clinical guidelines, Argument Comput. 12
infinite AF which makes information encoded within the                (2021) 149–189.
knowledge base explicit. One could therefore examine             [11] X. Fan, F. Toni, A. Mocanu, M. Williams, Dialog-
whether our results translate to other formalisms as well.            ical two-agent decision making with assumption-
                                                                      based argumentation, in: Proc. AAMAS, IFAA-
                                                                      MAS/ACM, 2014, pp. 533–540.
                                                                 [12] L. Amgoud, P. Besnard, S. Vesic, Equivalence in




                                                             102
οΏ½     logic-based argumentation, J. Appl. Non Class. Log-        interface, Int. J. Approx. Reason. 112 (2019) 55–84.
     ics 24 (2014) 181–208.                                [27] P. M. Thang, P. M. Dung, J. Pooksook, Infinite argu-
[13] T. Lehtonen, J. P. Wallner, M. JΓ€rvisalo, From struc-      ments and semantics of dialectical proof procedures,
     tured to abstract argumentation: Assumption-based          Argument Comput. (2021). In-press.
     acceptance via AF reasoning, in: Proc. ECSQARU,
     volume 10369 of LNCS, Springer, 2017, pp. 57–68.
[14] B. Yun, N. Oren, M. Croitoru, Efficient con-
     struction of structured argumentation systems, in:
     Proc. COMMA, volume 326 of FAIA, IOS Press,
     2020, pp. 411–418.
[15] M. Thimm, S. Villata, The first international com-
     petition on computational models of argumentation:
     Results and analysis, Artif. Intell. 252 (2017) 267–
     294.
[16] S. A. Gaggl, T. Linsbichler, M. Maratea, S. Woltran,
     Design and results of the second international com-
     petition on computational models of argumentation,
     Artif. Intell. 279 (2020).
[17] R. Craven, F. Toni,          Argument graphs and
     assumption-based argumentation, Artif. Intell. 233
     (2016) 1–59.
[18] W. DvoΕ™Γ‘k, P. E. Dunne, Computational problems
     in formal argumentation and their complexity, in:
     P. Baroni, D. Gabbay, M. Giacomin, L. van der
     Torre (Eds.), Handbook of Formal Argumentation,
     College Publications, 2018.
[19] D. S. Johnson, C. H. Papadimitriou, M. Yannakakis,
     On generating all maximal independent sets, Inf.
     Process. Lett. 27 (1988) 119–123.
[20] Z. Bao, K. Čyras, F. Toni, ABAplus: Attack reversal
     in abstract and structured argumentation with pref-
     erences, in: Proc. PRIMA, volume 10621 of LNCS,
     Springer, 2017, pp. 420–437.
[21] B. Yun, S. Vesic, M. Croitoru, Toward a more effi-
     cient generation of structured argumentation graphs,
     in: Proc. COMMA, volume 305 of FAIA, IOS Press,
     2018, pp. 205–212.
[22] Y. Dimopoulos, B. Nebel, F. Toni, On the computa-
     tional complexity of assumption-based argumenta-
     tion for default reasoning, Artif. Intell. 141 (2002)
     57–78.
[23] K. Čyras, Q. Heinrich, F. Toni, Computational com-
     plexity of flat and generic assumption-based argu-
     mentation, with and without probabilities, Artif.
     Intell. 293 (2021) 103449.
[24] T. Lehtonen, J. P. Wallner, M. JΓ€rvisalo, Declarative
     algorithms and complexity results for assumption-
     based argumentation, J. Artif. Intell. Res. 71 (2021)
     265–318.
[25] A. Karamlou, K. Čyras, F. Toni, Complexity re-
     sults and algorithms for bipolar argumentation, in:
     Proc. AAMAS, IFAAMAS, 2019, pp. 1713–1721.
[26] H. Strass, A. Wyner, M. Diller, EMIL: Extract-
     ing meaning from inconsistent language: Towards
     argumentation using a controlled natural language




                                                        103
οΏ½