Vol-3197/short2

From BITPlan ceur-ws Wiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Paper

Paper
edit
description  scientific paper published in CEUR-WS Volume 3197
id  Vol-3197/short2
wikidataid  Q117341470โ†’Q117341470
title  Abductive Reasoning with Sequent-Based Argumentation
pdfUrl  https://ceur-ws.org/Vol-3197/short2.pdf
dblpUrl  https://dblp.org/rec/conf/nmr/ArieliBHS22
volume  Vol-3197โ†’Vol-3197
session  โ†’

Freitext

Abductive Reasoning with Sequent-Based Argumentation

load PDF

Abductive Reasoning with Sequent-Based Argumentation
(Extended Abstract)

Ofer Arieli1 , AnneMarie Borg2 , Matthis Hesse3 and Christian StraรŸer3
1
  School of Computer Science, Tel-Aviv Academic College, Israel
2
  Department of Information and Computing Sciences, Utrecht University, The Netherlands
3
  Institute for Philosophy II, Ruhr University Bochum, Germany


                                             Abstract
                                             We show that logic-based argumentation, and in particular sequent-based frameworks, is a robust argumentative setting for
                                             abductive reasoning and explainable artificial intelligence.


1. Introduction                                                                                                                       monotonic (if ๐’ฎ โ€ฒ โŠข ๐œ‘ and ๐’ฎ โ€ฒ โŠ† ๐’ฎ, then ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ‘), and tran-
                                                                                                                                      sitive (if ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ‘ and ๐’ฎ โ€ฒ , ๐œ‘ โŠข ๐œ“ then ๐’ฎ, ๐’ฎ โ€ฒ โŠข ๐œ“).
Abduction is the process of deriving a set of explanations
                                                                                                                                      โˆ™ The language L contains at least a โŠข-negation opera-
of a given observation relative to a set of assumptions.
                                                                                                                                      tor ยฌ, satisfying ๐‘ ฬธโŠข ยฌ๐‘ and ยฌ๐‘ ฬธโŠข ๐‘ (for atomic ๐‘), and
The systematic study of abductive reasoning goes back
                                                                                                                                      a โŠข-conjunction operator โˆง, forโ‹€๏ธ€    which ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ“ โˆง ๐œ‘ iff
to Peirce (see [1]). Abduction is closely related to โ€˜in-
                                                                                                                                      ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ“ and ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ‘. We denote by ฮ“ the conjunction of
ference to the best explanation (IBE)โ€™ [2]. However, it is
                                                                                                                                      the formulas in ฮ“. We sometimes assume the availability
often distinguished from the latter in that abductive infer-
                                                                                                                                      of a deductive implication โ†’, satisfying ๐’ฎ, ๐œ“ โŠข ๐œ‘ iff
ence may provide explanations that are not known as the
                                                                                                                                      ๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ“ โ†’ ๐œ‘.
best explanation available, but that are merely worthy of
                                                                                                                                         A set ๐’ฎ of formulas is โŠข-consistent, if there are no
conjecturing or entertaining (see, e.g., [3, 4, 5]).
                                                                                                                                      formulas ๐œ‘1 , . . . , ๐œ‘๐‘› โˆˆ ๐’ฎ for which โŠข ยฌ(๐œ‘1 โˆง ยท ยท ยท โˆง ๐œ‘๐‘› ).
   In this work, we model abduction (not in the strict
sense of IBE) by computational argumentation, and show                                                                                โˆ™ Arguments based on a logic L = โŸจL, โŠขโŸฉ are single-
that sequent-based argumentation frameworks [6, 7] are                                                                                conclusioned L-sequents [8], i.e., expressions of the form
a solid argumentative base for abductive reasoning. Ac-                                                                               ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ“, where โ‡’ is a symbol that does not appear in L,
cording to our approach, abductive explanations are han-                                                                              and such that ฮ“ โŠข ๐œ“. ฮ“ is called the argumentโ€™s support
dled by ingredients of the framework, and so different                                                                                (also denoted Supp(ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ“)) and ๐œ“ is its conclusion
considerations and principles concerning those explana-                                                                               (denoted Conc(ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ“)). An ๐’ฎ-based argument is an L-
tions are expressed within the framework. The advantages                                                                              argument ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ“, where ฮ“ โŠ† ๐’ฎ. We denote by ArgL(๐’ฎ)
of this are discussed in the last section of the paper.                                                                               the set of the L-arguments that are based on ๐’ฎ.
                                                                                                                                         We distinguish between two types of premises: a โŠข-
                                                                                                                                      consistent set ๐’ณ of strict premises, and a set ๐’ฎ of defea-
2. Sequent-Based Argumentation                                                                                                        sible premises. We write Arg๐’ณ L (๐’ฎ) for ArgL(๐’ณ โˆช ๐’ฎ).

We denote by L a propositional language. Atomic formu-                                                                                โˆ™ Attack rules are sequent-based inference rules for rep-
las in L are denoted by ๐‘, ๐‘ž, ๐‘Ÿ, formulas are denoted by                                                                              resenting attacks between sequents. Such rules consist
๐œ‘, ๐œ“, ๐›ฟ, ๐›พ, ๐œ–, sets of formulas are denoted by ๐’ณ , ๐’ฎ, โ„ฐ, and                                                                          of an attacking argument (the first condition of the rule),
finite sets of formulas are denoted by ฮ“, โˆ†, ฮ , ฮ˜, all of                                                                             an attacked argument (the last condition of the rule), con-
which can be primed or indexed. The set of atomic formu-                                                                              ditions for the attack (the other conditions of the rule)
las appearing in the formulas of ๐’ฎ is denoted Atoms(๐’ฎ).                                                                               and a conclusion (the eliminated attacked sequent). The
The set of the (well-formed) formulas of L is denoted                                                                                 elimination of ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ‘ is denoted by ฮ“ ฬธโ‡’ ๐œ‘.
WFF(L), and its power set is denoted โ„˜(WFF(L)).                                                                                          Given a set ๐’ณ of strict (non-attacked) formulas, we
                                                                                                                                      shall concentrate here on the following two attack rules:
โˆ™ The base logic is an arbitrary propositional logic,
namely a pair L = โŸจL, โŠขโŸฉ consisting of a language L Direct Defeat (for ๐›พ ฬธโˆˆ ๐’ณ ):
and a consequence relation โŠข on โ„˜(WFF(L))ร—WFF(L).                         ฮ“1 โ‡’ ๐œ“1 ๐œ“1 โ‡’ ยฌ๐›พ ฮ“2 , ๐›พ โ‡’ ๐œ“2
The relation โŠข is assumed to be reflexive (๐’ฎ โŠข ๐œ‘ if ๐œ‘ โˆˆ ๐’ฎ),                       ฮ“2 , ๐›พ ฬธโ‡’ ๐œ“2
                                                                                                                                      Consistency Undercut (for ฮ“2 ฬธ= โˆ…, ฮ“2 โˆฉ๐’ณ = โˆ…, ฮ“1 โŠ†๐’ณ ):
                                                                                                                                                                                      ฮ“2 , ฮ“โ€ฒ2 โ‡’ ๐œ“
                                                                                                                                                                            โ‹€๏ธ€
NMR 2022: 20th International Workshop on Non-Monotonic Reasoning,                                                                                                  ฮ“1 โ‡’ ยฌ        ฮ“2
August 7-9, 2022, Haifa, Israel
                                       ยฉ 2022 Copyright for this paper by its authors. Use permitted under Creative Commons License                                        ฮ“2 , ฮ“โ€ฒ2 ฬธโ‡’ ๐œ“
                                       Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0).
    CEUR
    Workshop
    Proceedings
                  http://ceur-ws.org
                  ISSN 1613-0073
                                       CEUR Workshop Proceedings (CEUR-WS.org)




                                                                                                                                143
๏ฟฝDirect Defeat (DirDef) indicates that if the conclusion                     E1                              E2
(๐œ“1 ) of the attacker entails the negation of a formula (๐›พ)
                                                                  clear_skies โ‡’ clear_skies             rainy โ‡’ rainy
in the support of an argument, the latter is eliminated.
When ฮ“1 = โˆ…, consistency undercut (ConUcut) elimi-                      clear_skies,                        rainy,
                                                                    clear_skies โ†’ ยฌrainy             rainy โ†’ ยฌsprinklers
nates an argument with an inconsistent support.                           โ‡’ ยฌrainy                      โ‡’ ยฌsprinklers

โˆ™ A (sequent-based) argumentation framework (AF),                                                            rainy,
based on the logic L and the attack rules in AR, for a set                                           clear_skies โ†’ ยฌrainy

of defeasible premises ๐’ฎ and a โŠข-consistent set of strict                   wet_grass โ‡
                                                                                                        โ‡’ ยฌclear_skies

premises ๐’ณ , is a pair AFL,AR (๐’ฎ) = โŸจArgL (๐’ฎ), AโŸฉ where
                            ๐’ณ                 ๐’ณ
                                                                             [sprinkler],                    rainy,
                                                                       sprinklers โ†’ wet_grass          rainy โ†’ wet_grass
A โŠ† Arg๐’ณ  L  (๐’ฎ)ร—Arg   ๐’ณ
                       L  (๐’ฎ) and (๐‘Ž1 , ๐‘Ž 2 ) โˆˆ A iff there  is a                                         โ‡’ wet_grass
rule R๐’ณ โˆˆ AR, such that ๐‘Ž1 R๐’ณ -attacks ๐‘Ž2 . We shall use
AR and A interchangeably, denoting both of them by A. Figure 1: Part of the AF of Example 1 (without the gray node)
โˆ™ Semantics of sequent-based frameworks are defined as and of Example 2 (with the gray node).
usual by Dung-style extensions [9]: Let AF = AF๐’ณ         L,A (๐’ฎ)
= โŸจArg๐’ณ  L  (๐’ฎ), AโŸฉ  be  an AF  and  let  E   โŠ†  Arg  ๐’ณ
                                                      L (๐’ฎ).    E
attacks ๐‘Ž if there is an ๐‘Žโ€ฒ โˆˆ E such that (๐‘Žโ€ฒ , ๐‘Ž) โˆˆ A. E
defends ๐‘Ž if E attacks every attacker of ๐‘Ž, and E is conflict- (since the argument rainy, rainy โ†’ wet_grass โ‡’
free (cf) if for no ๐‘Ž1 , ๐‘Ž2 โˆˆ E it holds that (๐‘Ž1 , ๐‘Ž2 ) โˆˆ A. wet_grass is in E2 ), but it is not skeptically deducible
E is admissible if it is conflict-free and defends all of (there is no ๐‘Ž โˆˆ E1 such that Conc(๐‘Ž) = wet_grass).
its elements. A complete (cmp) extension of AF is an
admissible set that contains all the arguments that it
defends. The grounded (grd) extension of AF is the โŠ†-
minimal complete extension of Arg๐’ณ
                                                                  3. Abductive Reasoning
                                      L (๐’ฎ), a preferred (prf)
extension of AF is a โŠ†-maximal complete extension of For supporting abductive explanations in sequent-based
Arg๐’ณ L (๐’ฎ), and a stable (stb) extension of AF is a conflict- argumentation, we introduce abductive sequents, which
free set in Arg๐’ณ L (๐’ฎ) that attacks every argument not in         are expressions of the form ๐œ‘ โ‡ ฮ“, [๐œ–], intuitively mean-
it.1 We denote by Extsem (AF) the set of all the extensions ing that โ€˜(the explanandum) ๐œ‘ may be inferred from ฮ“,
of AF of type sem.                                                assuming that ๐œ– holdsโ€™. While ฮ“ โŠ† ๐’ฎ โˆช ๐’ณ , ๐œ– may not be
โˆ™ Entailments of AF = AF๐’ณ                     ๐’ณ
                              L,A (๐’ฎ) = โŸจArgL (๐’ฎ), AโŸฉ        an assumption, but rather a hypothetical explanation of
with respect to a semantics sem are defined as follows:      the conclusion.
โˆ˜ Skepticalโ‹‚๏ธ€entailment: ๐’ฎ |โˆผโˆฉ,sem   ๐œ‘  if there is an argu-   Abductive sequents are produced by the following rule
                               L,A,๐’ณ
ment ๐‘Ž โˆˆ Extsem (AF) such that Conc(๐‘Ž) = ๐œ‘.                  that models abduction as โ€˜backwards reasoningโ€™:

                                       L,A,๐’ณ ๐œ‘ if for every
โˆ˜ Weakly skeptical entailment: ๐’ฎ |โˆผโ‹’,sem                                                                  ๐œ–, ฮ“ โ‡’ ๐œ‘
                                                             โ€ข Abduction:
extension E โˆˆ Extsem (AF) there is an argument ๐‘Ž โˆˆ E                                                      ๐œ‘ โ‡ ฮ“, [๐œ–]
such that Conc(๐‘Ž) = ๐œ‘.
                               โˆช,sem                           This rule allows us to produce abductive sequents like
โˆ˜ Credulous โ‹ƒ๏ธ€entailment: ๐’ฎ |โˆผL,A,๐’ณ ๐œ‘ iff there is an argu- wet_grass โ‡ [sprinklers], sprinklers โ†’ wet_
ment ๐‘Ž โˆˆ Extsem (AF) such that Conc(๐‘Ž) = ๐œ‘.                  grass that provides an explanation to wet_grass.
Example 1. Consider a sequent-based AF, based on               Since abductive reasoning is a form of non-monotonic
classical logic CL and the set ๐’ฎ of defeasible assumptions: reasoning, we need a way to attack abductive sequents.
                                                             To this end, we consider rules like those from Section 2:
  โŽจ clear_skies, rainy, clear_skies โ†’ ยฌrainy, โŽฌ
  โŽง                                                     โŽซ

    rainy โ†’ ยฌsprinklers, rainy โ†’ wet_grass,               โ€ข Abductive Direct Defeat (for ๐›พ โˆˆ (ฮ“2 โˆช {๐œ–}) โˆ– ๐’ณ ):
    sprinklers โ†’ wet_grass
  โŽฉ                                           โŽญ
                                                                             ฮ“1 โ‡’ ๐œ‘1 ๐œ‘1 โ‡’ ยฌ๐›พ ๐œ‘2 โ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2
  Suppose further that ๐’ณ = โˆ… and the attack rules are                                   ๐œ‘2 ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2
DirDef and ConUcut. Then, for instance, the arguments
                                                          Note that this attack rule assures, in particular, the con-
๐‘Ž1 : clear_skies, clear_skies โ†’ ยฌrainy โ‡’ ยฌrainy
                                                          sistency of explanations with the strict assumptions, thus
๐‘Ž2 : rainy, clear_skies โ†’ ยฌrainy โ‡’ ยฌclear_skies
                                                          it renders the following rule admissible:
DirDef-attack each other. There are two stable/preferred
extensions E1 and E2 , where ๐‘Ž1 โˆˆ E1 and ๐‘Ž2 โˆˆ E2 (see โ€ข Consistency (for ฮ“ โŠ† ๐’ณ ): ฮ“1 โ‡’ ยฌ๐œ– ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2
                                                                                1
Fig. 1). Thus, with respect to stable or preferred seman-                                        ๐œ‘ ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2
tics, wet_grass credulously follows from the framework
                                                             Abductive explanations should meet certain require-
1
  For an in-depth discussion of extension types see [10]. ments to ensure their behavior (see, e.g., [11]). Below,




                                                           144
๏ฟฝwe express some of the common properties in terms of           โˆ˜ weakly-skeptical sem-explanation of ๐œ‘, if in every sem-
attack rules that may be added to the framework.               extension
                                                                     โ‹€๏ธ€ of AAFL,Aโ‹†(๐’ฎ) there is an abductive argument
                                                                                 ๐’ณ

                                                               ๐œ‘ โ‡ [ โ„ฐ], ฮ“ for some ฮ“ โŠ† ๐’ฎ.
                                      โŠข ๐œ– โ†’ ๐œ‘ ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–]
โ€ข Non Vacuousity:                                              โˆ˜ credulous sem-explanation  of ๐œ‘, if there is ฮ“ โŠ† ๐’ฎ
                                           ๐œ‘ ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–]
                                                               such that ๐œ‘ โ‡ [ โ„ฐ], ฮ“ is in some sem-extension of
                                                                                 โ‹€๏ธ€
This rule prevents self-explanations. Thus, in the running     AAF๐’ณ L,Aโ‹†(๐’ฎ).
example, wet_grass โ‡ [wet_grass] is excluded.
                                                           Example 2. As mentioned, the abductive sequent wet_
โ€ข Minimality:                                              grass โ‡ [sprinklers], sprinklers โ†’ wet_grass
      ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–1 ], ฮ“ ๐œ–2 โ‡’ ๐œ–1 ๐œ–1 ฬธโ‡’ ๐œ–2 ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–2 ], ฮ“           is producible by Abduction from the sequent-based frame-
                                                           work in Example 1, and belongs to a stable/preferred
                      ๐œ‘ ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–2 ], ฮ“                        extension of the related abductive sequent-based frame-
This rule assures the generality of explanations. Thus, in work (see again Fig. 1). Therefore, sprinklers is a cred-
our example, sprinklers โˆง irrelevant_fact should ulous (but not [weakly] skeptical) stb/prf-explaination
not explain wet_grass, since sprinklers is a more gen- of wet_grass.
eral and so more relevant explanation.                     Example 3. Let L = CL, A = {DirDef, ConUcut}
                                  ฮ“1 โ‡’ ๐œ‘ ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2                 with ๐’ฎ = {๐‘, ยฌ๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž} and ๐’ณ = {๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘ }. For sem โˆˆ
โ€ข Defeasible Non-Idleness:                                           {stb, prf}, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ is a weakly-skeptical sem-explanation
                                      ๐œ‘ ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2
                                                                     of ๐‘ , since the corresponding abductive framework has
                                        ฮ“1 โ‡’ ๐œ‘ ๐œ‘ โ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2           two sem-extensions, one with ๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ], ๐‘, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘ 
โ€ข Strict Non-Idleness (ฮ“1 โŠ† ๐’ณ ):
                                               ๐œ‘ ฬธโ‡ [๐œ–], ฮ“2          and the other with ๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ], ยฌ๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘ . This
                                                                     holds also when the non-vacuousity or the strict non-
The two rules above assure that assumptions shouldnโ€™t al- idleness attack rules are part of the framework. However,
ready explain the explanandum. Defeasible non-idleness ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ is no longer a weakly-skeptical sem-explanation of
rules out explaining wet_grass by sprinklers, since ๐‘  when minimality attack is added, since the extension
the former is already inferred from the defeasible assump- that contains ๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ], ยฌ๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘  includes a
tions (assuming that it is rainy), while strict non-idleness minimality attacker, ๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘Ÿ], ยฌ๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘ .
allows this alternative explanation (wet_grass cannot
be inferred from the strict assumptions). These two at- Example 4. Consider now ๐’ฎ = {๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž, ยฌ๐‘ โˆง ๐‘ž}. This
tack rules are particularly interesting when abductive time, with minimality, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ is not even a credulous
reasoning is used to generate novel hypotheses explain- sem-explanation of ๐‘  (sem โˆˆ {stb, prf}), since each of
ing observations that are not already explained by a given the two sem-extensions contains a minimality attacker
theory resp. the given background assumptions.2                      (๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘Ÿ], ๐‘โˆง๐‘ž, ๐‘ž โˆง๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘  or ๐‘  โ‡ [๐‘Ÿ], ยฌ๐‘โˆง๐‘ž, ๐‘ž โˆง๐‘Ÿ โ†’ ๐‘ ).
                                                                     So, ๐‘ž โˆง ๐‘Ÿ, unlike ๐‘Ÿ, does not sem-explain ๐‘ .
    Next, we adapt sequent-based argumentation frame-
works to an abductive setting, using abductive sequents,
the new inference rule, and additional attack rules.                 4. Discussion and Conclusion
    Given a sequent-based framework AF๐’ณ             L,A (๐’ฎ), an  ab-
                                                                     Abduction has been widely applied in different deduc-
ductive sequent-based framework AAF๐’ณ           L,Aโ‹†(๐’ฎ) is construc-
ted by adding to the arguments in ArgL (๐’ฎ) also abduc- tive systems (such as adaptive logics [12]) and AI-based
                                                 ๐’ณ

tive arguments, produced by Abduction, and where Aโ‹† is disciplines (e.g., logic programing [13]), including in the
obtained by adding to the attack rules in A also (some of) context of formal argumentation (see the survey in [14]).
the rules for maintaining explanations that are described               This ongoing work offers several novelties. In terms
above. Explanations are then defined as follows:                     of knowledge representation we transparently represent
                                                                     abductive inferences by an explicit inference rule that
Definition 1. Let AAF๐’ณ         L,Aโ‹†(๐’ฎ) be an abductive sequent- produces abductive arguments. The latter are a new type
based argumentation framework as described above. A of hypothetical arguments that are subjected to poten-
finite set โ„ฐ of L-formulas is called:                                tial defeats. Specifically designed attack rules address
                                                                     the quality of the offered explanation and thereby model
         โ‹€๏ธ€ sem-explanation of ๐œ‘, if there is ฮ“ ๐’ณโŠ† ๐’ฎ s.t. critical questions [15] and meta-argumentative reason-
โˆ˜ skeptical
๐œ‘ โ‡ [ โ„ฐ], ฮ“ is in every sem-extension of AAFL,Aโ‹†(๐’ฎ).
                                                                     ing [16]. This is both natural and philosophically moti-
2
  In some accounts of abduction, e.g. [5], it is argued that the ab- vated, as argued in [17]. Our framework offers a high
  ductively inferred ๐œ– should be of lesser epistemic status than the degree of modularity, and may be based on a variety of
  reasonerโ€™s starting point and so โ€œthe fundamental conceptual fact
  about abduction is that abduction is ignorance-preserving reason- propositional logics. Desiderata on abductive arguments
  ingโ€ (p. 40). Our attack rules ensure that the reasoner faces what can be disambiguated in various ways by simply chang-
  Gabbay & Woods call an โ€˜ignorance problemโ€™ (p. 42, Def. 3.2).      ing the attack rules, all in the same base framework.




                                                            145
๏ฟฝReferences                                                     of explanatory hypotheses: an argumentative ap-
                                                               proach, Logic Journal of the IGPL 29(4) (2021) 523โ€“
 [1] C. S. Peirce, The Collected Papers of Charles             535.
     Sanders Peirce, Vol. I: The Principles of Philosophy,
     Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1931.
 [2] P. Lipton, Inference to the Best Explanation, Rout-
     ledge, 2004. 2nd edition.
 [3] S. Yu, F. Zenker, Peirce knew why abduction isnโ€™t
     IBE โ€” A scheme and critical questions for abductive
     argument, Argumentation 32 (2017) 569โ€“587.
 [4] G. Minnameier, Peirce-suit of truth โ€“ Why infer-
     ence to the best explanation and abduction ought
     not to be confused, Erkenntnis 60 (2004) 75โ€“105.
 [5] D. Gabbay, J. Woods, The reach of abduction. A
     practical logic of cognitive systems, North-Holland,
     2005.
 [6] O. Arieli, C. StraรŸer, Sequent-based logical argu-
     mentation, Argument & Computation 6 (2015) 73โ€“
     99.
 [7] A. Borg, Assumptive sequent-based argumenta-
     tion, Journal of Applied Logics โ€“ IfCoLog Journal
     of Logics and Their Applications 7 (2020) 227โ€“294.
 [8] G. Gentzen, Untersuchungen รผber das logische
     schlieรŸen I, II, Mathematische Zeitschrift 39 (1934)
     176โ€“210, 405โ€“431.
 [9] P. M. Dung, On the acceptability of arguments and
     its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning,
     logic programming and n-person games, Artificial
     Intelligence 77 (1995) 321โ€“357.
[10] P. Baroni, M. Caminada, M. Giacomin, Abstract
     argumentation frameworks and their semantics, in:
     P. Baroni, D. Gabbay, M. Giacomin, L. van der Torre
     (Eds.), Handbook of Formal Argumentation, vol-
     ume 1, College Publications, 2018, pp. 159โ€“236.
[11] J. Meheus, L. Verhoeven, M. Van Dyck, D. Provijn,
     Ampliative adaptive logics and the foundation of
     logic-based approaches to abduction, Logical and
     Computational Aspects of Model-Based Reasoning
     25 (2002) 39โ€“71.
[12] J. Meheus, D. Batens, A formal logic for abductive
     reasoning, Logic Journal of the IGPL 14 (2006) 221โ€“
     236.
[13] M. Denecker, A. Kakas, Abduction in logic pro-
     gramming, in: Computational Logic: Logic Pro-
     gramming and Beyond, LNCS 2407, Springer, 2002,
     pp. 402โ€“436.
[14] K. Cyras, A. Rago, E. Albini, P. Baroni, F. Toni, Ar-
     gumentative XAI: A survey, in: Proc. 30th IJCAI,
     2021, pp. 4392โ€“4399.
[15] D. Walton, C. Reed, F. Macagno, Argumentation
     Schemes, Cambridge University Press, 2008.
[16] G. Boella, D. Gabbay, L. van der Torre, S. Villata,
     Meta-argumentation modelling I: Methodology and
     techniques, Studia Logica 93 (2009) 297โ€“355.
[17] P. Olmos, Abduction and comparative weighing




                                                         146
๏ฟฝ